117382 Kansas city public library Books /.ill be issued only on presentation of library card. Please report lost cards and change of residence pron.ptly. Card holders are responsible for all bo ks. records, filn s. pictures checked DIDEROT'S EARLY PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS Frontispiece. The Open Court Series of Classics of Science and Philosophy^ 2{o. 4 DIDEROT'S EARLY PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS TRANSLATED AND EDITED BY MARGARET JOURDAIN CHICAGO AND LONDON THE OPEN COURT PUBLISHING COMPANY 1916 z>/ Great JBr-ffazn vtyzde?- f7i& TABLE OF CONTENTS PAGE INTRODUCTION ....... i PHILOSOPHIC THOUGHTS 27 LETTER ON THE BLIND .68 ADDITION TO THE LETTER ON THE BLIND . . 142 LETTER ON THE DEAF AND DUMB . . .158 NOTES . 219 APPENDIX . 226 INDEX ......... 245 DIDEROT'S EARLY PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS INTRODUCTION DIDEROT A COMPLETE survey of the life and works of Diderot whom Voltaire called Pantophile is not attempted here, for the list of the topics he handled would be a very long one, including as it does various depart- ments of art and science and speculation. The Letter on the Blind (the most interesting of his early works), however, shows him in two lights as a free-thinker and as one of the long succession of thinkers who prepared the way for the theory of evolution. The agitation caused by Diderot and his circle about the theory of transformism, it has been said, must have largely contributed to awaken the attention of Erasmus Darwin in England and Lamarck in France to the necessity of throwing more positive light on that great issue. Transformism only needed the partial scientific confirmation which Lamarck and Geoffroy St Hilaire gave it in the first two decades of the nineteenth century to pass from the realm of systematic philosophy into that of 2 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS scientific controversy. Lamarck, who was for some time the protege of Buffon, and in 1785 became a contributor to the Methodic Encyclopedia' 1 (edited by Naigeon and other friends of Diderot), eventu- ally founded transformism when he subjected it to definite laws. 2 Throughout the Letter on the Blind, and indeed throughout Diderot's work, is apparent his indebtedness to English thought ; then, and in later life, he was the most English of Frenchmen the man who could write to Catherine II. in 1775 that "it is obvious to all who have eyes in their head, that if it had not been for the English, reason and philosophy would be still in the most pitiable and rudimentary condition in France." In Brune- tiere's words, "There is no trace of anything but England in the work of the man who has often been ' described as the most German of Frenchmen. " 3 Denis Diderot was born at Langres on October 5th, 1713. He was educated by the Jesuits, and threw himself into the Bohemian life of a bookseller's hack in Paris. His early writings were mere hackwork a translation of Stanyan's History of Greece (1743), for which he earned 100 crowns, and a translation (with two collaborators) of James's Dictionary of Medicine ( 1 746-48). The rendering of Shaftesbury 's Inquiry concerning Virtue and Merit (1745) has some notes of his own. Besides his volume of stories, The Indiscreet Jewels (1748), he wrote the * JEncycbp/die Mtthodique. 3 R. L. Cm, Diderot and English Thought, New York, 1913. 3 F. Branettere, Manuel de thistoire de la literature francaise 1898, p. 321. J * ' INTRODUCTION 3 Philosophic Thoughts and The Sceptics Walk (1747) an allegory pointing to the extravagances of Catholicism and the uncertainty of philosophy. For his Letter on the Blind he was imprisoned at Vincennes. In a second piece, published after the Letter on the Blind, Diderot considered the case of the deaf and dumb. The Letter on tJie Deaf and Dumb, however, is an examination on some points in aesthetics, not a fragment of scientific speculation like the earlier Letter. On his release from imprisonment at Vincennes, at the instance of his bookseller he entered upon his life work, the Encydop&dia. In 1745 a bookseller, Le Breton, suggested to Diderot a book that should be all books. In 1750 appeared d'Alembert's pre- face, and the first volume appeared in 1751. For years the history of Diderot and the Encyclopedia was the same thing. ' * The thing will surely pro- duce a great revolution in the human mind," he said of it ; " we shall have served humanity." Diderot, who was not equal to the task of super- vising every department of this gigantic enterprise, associated with himself as colleague d'Alembert, to whom he turned for aid in the mathematical articles. D'Alembert withdrew from the venture in 1758, worn out with affronts and vexations of every kind ; and for seven years the labour of carrying the vast work to its close fell upon Diderot alone. Besides bis labours as editor, he contributed articles on a vast scale, so that his contributions fill more than four of the volumes of his collected works. The 4 DIDEROT'S PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS arguments against design would be as effective in the mouth of the sighted. He chooses as the mouth- piece of his scepticism the blind mathematician, Nicholas Saunderson, and for the conversation between that "very intelligent clergyman" Gervase Holmes and the dying mathematician he cites as his authority a Life of Saunderson by Dr Inchlif l which does not exist. The transference of Diderot's opinions to this imaginary English source of course had its advantages in the days when "faggots were afraid of the fire." His Saunderson resents the clergyman's summoning as evidence of design the magnificent spectacle of Nature. " I have been condemned to pass my life in darkness, and yet you cite wonders which I cannot understand, and which are only evidence for you and for those who see as you do. If you want to make me believe in God, you must make me touch Him." The clergyman replied that touch ought to be enough to reveal the divinity to him in the admirable mechanism of his organs. Saunderson replies that, f If this mechanism fills you with astonishment, that is perhaps because you are accustomed to treat as miraculous everything that strikes you as beyond your own powers. We think a certain phenomenon beyond human power. We cry out at once, * 'Tis the handiwork of God ' ; our vanity will stick at nothing less. Why can we 1 The title is "The Life and Character of Dr Nicholas Saunderson, late Lucasian Professor of the Mathematics in the University of Cambridge, by his disciple and friend William Inchlif esqr." Barring the fictitious Inchlif, the date and the place, all is transcribed from the title-Daene of the Eltm/mtx of Alsrpbra. INTRODUCTION 5 Sunday of 1746. They were ordered by the Parliament of Paris to be burnt, with some other books (July 7th). The edition of 1746, however, is not rare, and the Philosophic Thoughts were re- printed in France, and translated into German and Italian. They were frequently attacked and criti- cised ; among the hostile critiques being : Pensees philosophiques et pensees chrttiennes mises en paral- lele, La Haye, 1746 ; Pensees raisonnables opposees aux Pensees philosophiques, by Formey, Berlin (Amsterdam), 1749 ; Penstes philosophiques {fun citoyen de Montmartre, by Senemaud, 1756 ; Pensees philosophiques sur divers sujets, La Haye, 1761 ; and Lettres sur Vecrit intitute Pensees philosophiques et sur le livre des Mceurs, 1749. Diderot's little book was among those found in the possession of La Barre. In the Philosophic Thoughts Diderot still figures as a Deist, opposing his God to the God of Pietists and reading a lessoti to the atheist (Thoughts XXII and XXIII). In Thought LVIII he proffers a con- fession of faith in "the Roman, Catholic, and Apostolic Church " which evidently did not disarm his judges. This and other references to Christianity are " no more than ironical deference to established prejudices" (Morley, Diderot, vol. i, p. 48). As d'Alembert wrote of the Encyclopedia, " Time will enable people to distinguish what we have thought from what we have said." In Thought XX Diderot adduces the argument 6 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS from design as a proof of the existence of a God. In The Sceptics Walk, however (CEuvres, i, p. 229), his atheist puts the case against design as a proof of the existence of God very trenchantly, and in the Letter on the Blind (ibid., p. 311) Saunderson also makes an eloquent protest against the inadequacy of this proof. THE LETTER ON THE BLIND ~" The Letter on the Blind is described in the Encyclo- pedia x as a very subtle metaphysical work, contain- ing certain passages which may offend pious ears. This estimate still may stand to-day. The interest of the letter is twofold : firstly, the scientific dis- cussion, where he treats of the theory of vision, and of how far a modification of the senses would involve "a modification of the ordinary notions acquired by men who are normally en- dowed in their capacity for sensation " ; 2 secondly, the argument that the argument from design is very weak evidence for both blind and sighted men. The Letter is, as it claims, a discursive and familiar document rather than a scientific treatise ; and,- written as it was to fill the purse of Madame de Puisieux, the writer of some forgotten literary pieces and with some pretensions to bel esprit, her shadow often falls across its pages. Diderot broke 1 Art. Aveugle ; see Appendix I. 2 John Morley, Diderot and the Encyclopedists, London 1886 vol. i, pp. 85-86. ' INTRODUCTION 7 with this fifth-rate female scribbler in 1749, and there is little in her later life of interest. Madame Roland describes her as preserving in her old age the affec- tations of the bel esprit. " I had imagined an authoress ought to be a very respectable personage, " she adds ; ' but the absurdities of Madame de Puisieux gave me food for reflection." 1 For the purpose of following the argument of the Letter^ it will be convenient to divide it into the two sections above mentioned. Voltaire's popularisation of the philosophy of Newton (1738) had stimulated scientific theory and research in France ; and in the seventh chapter of the second part of the Elements he describes Cheselden's operation for cataract on a blind lad, who was for a long time after his eyes were couched unable to distinguish objects by size, shape, or distance. Condillac, in 1/46, devoted a section in his Essay on the Origin of Human Knowledge* to the problem of the vision of the born blind ; and in 1748, when Reaumur couched the eyes of a blind girl, Diderot, with other men of science, wished to make a profitable use of the experiment. Excluded from the first experi- ment, Diderot turned his attention to personal observation and philosophical interrogatory of blind persons such as the man of Puisaux and (in the appendix written in later life) of Mademoiselle Mlanie de Salignac. Of the more famous Nicholas s^ vol. i, p. 157. 3 Mssai sur Vorigine des coiinaissanees Aumaznes, part i, vi (pp. 232-256 in (Euvrcs de Condillac^ 1798, vol. i). 8 DIDEROT'S PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS Saunderson of Cambridge, Diderot only knew the facts given to the world in the memoir prefixed to Saunderson's Algebra. The blind man of Puisaux interpreted sight as a kind of touch, and, as touch only conveyed to him the notion of relief, a mirror was to him "an instrument which sets us in relief out of ourselves." The eyes were ' ' an organ on which the air produces the same effect as my stick upon my hand. " He would have been tempted, like Mademoiselle de Salignac, to regard the sighted as superior in in- telligence but for the development of the senses of hearing and touch which supplements the deficiencies of the blind. He did not " set any high value upon modesty ; and if it were not for the inclemency of the air, against which clothes are a protection, he would hardly understand their use " ; and Diderot supposes that the blind are, as a rule, lacking in humanity, as the visible signs of pain do not affect them. " Do not we ourselves cease to be compassionate when distance or the shiallness of the object produces on us the same effect as deprivation of sight upon the blind ? . . . Ah, madam, how different is the morality of a blind man from ours ; and how the morality of the deaf would differ from that of the blind ; and if a being should have a sense more than we have, how woefully imperfect would he find our morality!" It is characteristic of Diderot's alert benevolence that he threw out a hint as to the education of the blind by a language of touch, " whereas for want of such a language, communica- INTRODUCTION g tion is entirely broken between us and those who are born deaf, dumb, and blind." 1 Diderot comes to the conclusion that l * when the eyes of the born blind are opened for the first time to the light he will perceive nothing at all " ; that some time will be necessary for the eye to make experiments itself and in its own way and without the help of touch. Passing from the peculiarities of the senses of the blind, Diderot turns to the question originally propounded by Molyneux whether a blind man, who had learned to distinguish by touch a sphere from a cube, would instantly identify each if he received sight ? Molyneux answered this question in the negative, and Locke (who expressed agree- ment with his solution and admiration for Moly- neux' insight) was of opinion that the blind man would not distinguish these objects until he had identified by touch the source of his tactual im- pression a conclusion in harmony with modern doctrine. 2 Though in these speculations Diderot keeps strictly to the problem of blindness and its effects upon the intellect of the blind, his strongest 1 Girolamo Cardano, a sixteenth- century physician, conceived the idea that the blind could be taught to read and write by means of touch. About 1517 Francesco Lucas in Spain, and Rampazetto in Italy, made use of large letters cut in wood for instructing the blind. In 1767 Jacques Bernoulli, the Swiss savant, taught a blind girl to read, but the means of her instruction were not made known. 2 "This is in harmony with the modern doctrine that there is an inherited aptitude of structure (in the eye, for instance), but that experience is an essential condition to the development and perfecting of this aptitude.' 7 Morley, Diderot and the Encyclopedists >, vol. i, p. 90, note. io DIDEROT'S PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS arguments against design would be as effective in the mouth of the sighted. He chooses as the mouth- piece of his scepticism the blind mathematician, Nicholas Saunderson, and for the conversation between that "very intelligent clergyman" Gervase Holmes and the dying mathematician he cites as his authority a Life of Saunderson by Dr Inchlif l which does not exist. The transference of Diderot's opinions to this imaginary English source of course had its advantages in the days when "faggots were afraid of the fire." His Saunderson resents the clergyman's summoning as evidence of design the magnificent spectacle of Nature. " I have been condemned to pass my life in darkness, and yet you cite wonders which I cannot understand, and which are only evidence for you and for those who see as you do. If you want to make me believe in God, you must make me touch Him." The clergyman replied that touch ought to be enough to reveal the divinity to him in the admirable mechanism of his organs. Saunderson replies that, f If this mechanism fills you with astonishment, that is perhaps because you are accustomed to treat as miraculous everything that strikes you as beyond your own powers. We think a certain phenomenon beyond human power. We cry out at once, * 'Tis the handiwork of God ' ; our vanity will stick at nothing less. Why can we 1 The title is "The Life and Character of Dr Nicholas Saunderson, late Lucasian Professor of the Mathematics in the University of Cambridge, by his disciple and friend William Inchlif esqr." Barring the fictitious Inchlif, the date and the place, all is transcribed from the title-Daene of the Rhmtnts of Alsrpbra. INTRODUCTION 11 not season our talk with a little less pride and a little more philosophy ? If Nature offers us a knotty problem, let us leave it for what it is, without calling In to cut it the hand of a Being who then immediately becomes a new knot, and harder to untie than the first." The clergyman falls back upon the evidence of Newton, Clarke, and Leibniz. Saunderson says that, though Newton and others may be convinced of the admirable order of the present state of the universe, they must leave him freedom of opinion as to its earlier state where Holmes can confront him with no witnesses and eyes are useless. "If we went back (he continues) to the origin of things and scenes and perceived matter in motion and the evolution from chaos, we should meet with a number of shapeless creatures instead of a few creatures highly organised. I make no criticism on the present state of things, but I can ask you some questions as to the past. For instance, I may ask you, and Leibniz, Clarke and Newton, who told you that in the first instances of the formation of animals some were not headless or footless ? I may maintain that such an one had no stomach and another no intestines ; that some who seemed to promise a long duration from their possession of a stomach, palate, and teeth carne to an end owing to some defect of the heart or lungs ; that monsters mutually destroyed one another ; that all the defective combinations of matter disappeared, and that only those survived whose mechanism was not 12 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS deficient in any important particular, and who were able to support and perpetuate themselves. " In 1754 he was led to the same question in his Thoughts on the Interpretation of Nature^ "Just as in the animal and vegetable kingdoms an individual begins, increases, endures, decays, and passes away, might it not be the same for species as a -whole ? If we were not taught by our faith that animals came out of the Creator's hands as we see them, and if it were permitted to entertain the least doubt about their beginning and their end, might not the philosopher, left to his own thoughts, suspect that animality had its elements from all eternity mixed up and dispersed in the mass of matter; that these elements happen to encounter one another, because it was possible that it should happen ; that the embryo, formed of these elements, went through an infinite series of organisms and developments ; that in succession it acquired motion, sensations, ideas, thought, reflection, consciousness, sentiments, passions, signs, gestures, sounds, articulation, a language, laws, sciences, and arts ; that millions of years passed between each of these stages ; that it may perhaps undergo further develop- ments, may receive further additions which are unknown to us ; that it has had and will have a stationary state ; that it is receding or will recede from that state through an immensely long decay, during which its faculties will disappear from it as they had come ; that it will vanish from nature for 1 2, 57-58- INTRODUCTION 13 ever, or rather, that it will still exist in nature, but in a form and with faculties very different from those that we observe in it at this instant of duration? Religion saves us many wanderings and much toil." Continuing the conversation, Saunderson adds : " I conjecture, then, that in the beginning when matter in a state of ferment brought this world into being, creatures like myself were of very common occurrence. But might not worlds be in the same case ? How many faulty or incomplete worlds have been dispersed and perhaps formed again, and are dispersed at every instant in distant regions of space which I cannot touch nor you behold, but where motion continues, and will continue, to combine masses of matter, until they have found some ar- rangement in which they may finally persevere? O philosopher, travel with me to the limits of this universe, beyond the point where I feel, and you behold, organised beings, cast your eyes over this new ocean and search in its lawless, aimless agitations for vestiges of that intelligent Being whose wisdom fills you with such wonder and admiration here ! " The imaginary Saunderson becomes excited with this prolonged debate, and after an attack of delirium dies with the words Diderot^ vol. i, p. 107. 4 Tyler's Researches into the Early History of Mankind, chapters ii and iii. Lubbock's Origin of Civilisation^ chapter ix. THE notes accompanying this translation are signed as follows : (1) Notes from the original edition : signed (D = Diderot). (2) ,, Naigeon's edition ,, (N). (3) ,, Belin's edition ,, (B). (4) ,, Briere's edition ,, (Br). (5) ,, Assezat's edition (A). (6) Translator's notes ,, [ ]. PHILOSOPHIC THOUGHTS Quis leget haec. PKRS. Sat. i. 2. I WRITE of God ; I count on a very few readers ; and do not hope to find many in agreement with me. If these thoughts please nobody, they are certainly bad, but I should count them sorry stuff if they were to everybody's taste. I People are for ever declaiming against the passions ; they attribute to them all the pains that man endures, and forget that they are also the source of all his pleasures. It is an ingredient in man's constitution which cannot sufficiently be blessed and banned. It is considered as an affront to reason if one ventures to say a word in favour of its rivals ; yet it is passions alone, and strong passions, that can elevate the soul to great things. Without them, there is no sublime, either in morality or in achievement ; the fine arts return to puerility, and virtue becomes a pettifogging thing. II Sober passions make men commonplace. If I hang back before the enemy, when my country's 27 28 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS safety is at stake, I am but a poor citizen. My friendship is but self-regarding if my friend's peril leaves me considering my own danger. If life is dearer to me than my mistress, I am a poor lover. Ill Deadened passions degrade men of extraordinary quality. Constraint annihilates the grandeur and energy of nature. Look at that tree ; it is to the luxury of its branches that you owe the coolness and breadth of its shade, which you may enjoy until winter despoils it of its leafy honours. There is no more excellence in poetry, in painting, and in music when superstition has wrought upon the human temperament the effect of old age. IV It would be fortunate, people will say to me, for a man to have strong passions ? Certainly, if they are all in harmony. Establish a just harmony among them, and you need fear no convulsions and disorders. If hope be balanced by fear, the point of honour by love of life, the taste for pleasure by consideration for health, there will be no libertines, nor rufflers, nor poltroons. V It is the very height of madness to propose the ruin of the passions. A fine design, truly, in your devotee, to torment himself like a convict in order to desire nothing, love nothing, and feel nothing. PHILOSOPHIC THOUGHTS 29 He would end by becoming a monster, If he were to succeed. VI Can what is the object of my respect in one man be the object of my scorn in another ? Certainly not. Truth, independently of my caprices, should be the rule of my judgments, and I shall not call that quality a crime in one man which I admire as a virtue in another. Am I to think that the practice of self-improvement is to be restricted to some few, when nature and religion inculcate it on all alike ? Whence comes this monopoly ? If Pachomius did well in separating himself from the human race and burying himself in a wilderness, I may follow his example, and in imitating him I shall be equally virtuous ; and I see no reason why a hundred others may not have the same right. Yet it would be a strange sight to see an entire province, dismayed at the dangers of society, dis- persed in forests, the inhabitants living like wild beasts to sanctify themselves, and a thousand pillars rising above the ruins of all social affections ; a new race of Stylites stripping themselves from religious motives of all natural feelings, ceasing to be men and becoming statues in order to be true Christians. VII What voices, what cries, what groans! Who has shut up in dungeons all these piteous wretches ? What crimes have all these creatures committed? 30 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS Some beat their breasts with stones, others lacerate their body with iron nails, all express in their eyes regret, pain, and death. Who condemns them to such torments ? The God whom they have offended. Who then is this God ? A God full of goodness. But would a God full of goodness take pleasure in bathing himself in tears ? Are not these fears an insult to his kindness ? If criminals had to appease the fury of a tyrant, what more could they do ? VIII These are people of whom we ought not to say that they fear God, but that they are mortally afraid of him. IX Judging from the picture they paint of the Supreme Being, from his tendency to wrath, from the rigour of his vengeance, from certain comparisons of the ratio between those he abandons to perish and those to whom he deigns to stretch out a hand, the most upright soul would be tempted to wish that such a being did not exist. We would be happy enough in this world, if we were assured we had nothing to fear in another. The thought that a God did not exist has never terrified humanity, but the idea that a God such as is represented exists. X God must be imagined as neither too kind nor too cruel. Justice is the mean between clemency and PHILOSOPHIC THOUGHTS 31 cruelty, just as finite penalties are the mean between impunity and eternal punishment. XI I am aware that the sombre ideas of superstition are more generally approved of than accepted ; that there are pietists who do not think it necessary to hate themselves in order to love God, or to live as desperate wretches, in order to be religious ; their devotion is a smiling one, their wisdom very human ; but whence comes this difference in sentiment be- tween people who prostrate themselves before the same altars ? Can piety thus be subject to the law of temperament ? Alas ! it must be so. Its influence is only too apparent in the same devotee : he sees, in accordance with its variations, a jealous or a merciful God, and hell or heaven opening before him ; he trembles with fear or burns with love ; it is a fever with its hot and cold fits. XII Yes, I maintain that superstition is more of an insult to God than atheism. "I would rather," said Plutarch, " that people thought that a Plutarch never existed, than that they thought of Plutarch as unjust, choleric, inconstant, jealous and revenge- ful, and such as he would be sorry to be." XIII Only the deist can oppose the atheist. The superstitious man is not so strong an opponent. 32 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS His God is only a creature of the imagination. Besides difficulties of a material nature, he is exposed to those which result from the falsity of his notions. A C and a S would have been a thousand times more embarrassing to a Vanini than all the Nicoles and Pascals in the world. 1 XIV Pascal was an upright man, but he was timid and inclined to credulity. An elegant writer and a pro- found reasoner, he would doubtless have enlightened the world, if Providence had not abandoned him to people who sacrificed his talents to their own anti- pathies. How much it is to be regretted that he did not leave to the theologians of his day the task of settling their own disputes ; that he did not give himself up to the search for truth without reserve and without fear of offending God, by using all the intellect God had given him ! How regrettable that he took for his masters men who were not worthy to be his disciples ! One could say of him, as La Mothe said of La Fontaine, that he was foolish enough to think Arnauld, de Sacy, and Nicole better men than himself. XV ' * I tell you that there is no God ; that Creation is a fiction ; that the eternity of the universe is no P Vanini, 1585-1619, was executed at Toulouse in 1619, on the charge of atheism. The initials C and S stand for the two English deists, Cndworth and Shaftesbury. ] PHILOSOPHIC THOUGHTS 53 more of a difficulty than the eternity of spirit ; that because I do not see how motion could have caused this universe (though it keeps it going), it is ridiculous to solve the difficulty by supposing the existence of a being of whom I can have no real conception ; that if the wonders of the physical universe show some intelligence, the confusions in the moral order are the negations of a Providence. I tell you if everything is the work of a God, every- thing should be the best possible : for if everything is not the best possible, it is impotence or malevolence on the part of God. Therefore it is fortunate that I am not better informed as to his existence. If it were proved satisfactorily (and it is by no means proved) that all evil is the source of good, that it was for the best that Britannicus, the best of princes, perished, and that Nero, the worst of men, should reign, how is it possible to prove that it was impossible to attain the same ends without using such means ? To allow vice in order to throw virtue into relief is a poor advantage in comparison with its real disadvantage." That, says the atheist, is my case ; what have you to say to it? *' That I am a miserable wretch, and that if I had nothing to fear from God, I should not be disputing his existence" Let us leave such an answer to orators ; it may be untrue ; politeness forbids it and it has no savour of charity about it. Because a man is mistaken in his denial of God, should we insult him ? People only take refuge in invective when they run short of proofs. Of two 3 34 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS engaged in argument, it is a hundred to one that the man in the wrong will become angry. * e You thunder instead of answering," says Menippus to Jupiter; "are you then in the wrong?" XVI One day somebody asked a man if real atheists existed. Do. you think, he responded, that real Christians exist? XVII None of the vain speculations of metaphysics have the cogency of an argument ad hominem. In order to convince, it is sometimes only necessary to rouse the physical or moral instinct. The' Pyrrhonist was convinced by a stick that he was wrong in doubting his own existence. Cartouche, pistol in hand, might have taught Hobbes a similar lesson : "Your money or your life ; we are alone, I am the stronger, and between us there is no question of justice." XVIII It is not from the metaphysician that atheism has received its most vital attack. The sublime meditations of Malebranche and Descartes were less calculated to shake materialism than a single observation of Malpighi's. If this dangerous hypothesis is tottering at the present day, it is to experimental physics that the result is due. It is only in the works of Newton, of Muschenbroek, of PHILOSOPHIC THOUGHTS 35 Hartzoeker, and of Nieuwentit, that satisfactory proofs have been found of the existence of a reign of sovereign intelligence. Thanks to the works of these great men, the world is no longer a God ; it is a machine with its wheels, its cords, its pulleys, its springs, and its weights. XIX The subtilties ol ontology have at best made sceptics, and it was reserved for the knowledge of nature to make true deists. The discovery of germs alone has destroyed one of the most power- ful arguments of atheism. Whether motion be essential or accidental to matter, I am now con- vinced that its effects are limited to developments ; all experiments agree in proving to me that putrefaction alone never produced any organism. I can allow that the mechanism of the vilest insect is not less marvellous than that of man ; and I am not afraid of the inference that as an intestinal agitation of molecules is able to produce the one, it is probable that it has produced the other. If an atheist had maintained, two hundred years ago, that some day perhaps people would see men spring full-formed from the bowels of the earth just as we see a mass of insects swarm in putrefying flesh, I would like to know what a metaphysician would have had to say to him ? 1 1 Diderot here alludes to Redi's experiments about the generation of insects, and in the preceding Thought he alludes to the discoveries due to the telescope and microscope.- (A) 36 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS XX It was in vain that I made use of scholastic subtilties against the atheist ; he found among his feeble reasons one argument of some validity. " A multitude of useless verities are proved to me without any doubt," he said, "and the existence of God, the reality of moral good and moral evil, and the immortality of the soul are still problems for me. What ! Is it less important for me to be informed on these subjects than to be sure that the three angles of a triangle are together equal to two right angles ? " While like a skilful orator he made me taste the full bitterness of this reflection, I joined battle with him again with a question which must have appeared singular to a man flushed with his first success. "Are you a thinking being?" I asked. "Can you doubt it?" he answered with a pleased air. "Why not? What have I seen to prove it? Sounds and movements? But the philosopher sees the same in an animal to whom he denies the faculty of thought ; why should I allow you what Descartes refuses the ant? Externally, your actions are designed to give me that impres- sion ; I should be tempted to maintain that you do think, but reason suspends my judgment. Between external actions and thought my reason tells me there is no essential connection ; it is possible that your antagonist thinks no more than his watch ; must one take for a thinking being the first animal taught to speak ? Who has informed you that all PHILOSOPHIC THOUGHTS 37 men are not so many well-trained parrots ? " "That is very ingenious," he returned, " but it is not by motion or sounds but by the continuity of ideas, the connection between propositions, and the links of the argument that one must judge if a creature thinks. If there was a parrot which could answer every question, I should say at once that it was a thinking being. But what has this to do with the existence of a God? If you were to prove to me that the most intelligent man were perhaps but an automaton, should I be the more disposed to recognise an intelligent Being in nature ? " " That is my affair," said I ; "but admit that it would be madness not to credit your brother men with the faculty of thought?" "Of course, but what follows?" "It follows that if the universe but why drag in the universe ? if a butterfly's wing shows me proofs of an intelligence a thousand times stronger than the proof you have that your fellow- man thinks, it would be a thousand times more foolish to deny that God exists than to deny that your fellow-man thinks. I appeal to your know- ledge, to your conscience ! Have you ever observed in any man more intelligence, order, wisdom, and reasonableness than in the mechanism of an insect ? Is not the Deity as clearly apparent in the eye of a flesh-worm as in the works of the great Newton ? What, does the formation of the world afford less proof of intelligence than its explana- tion ? What a position ! " " But," you reply, ' ' I admit the", faculty of thought in another the more 38 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS readily as I myself think. " That is an analogy I admit I cannot use, but against this must be set the superiority of my proofs to yours. Is not the intelligence of a first cause more conclusively proved in nature by his works than the faculty of reasoning in a philosopher by his writings? Remember, I only adduced a butterfly's wing, a flesh-worm's eye, when I could crush you with the weight of the entire universe. I am greatly deceived if this proof is not well worth the best that has ever issued from the schools. It is by this argument, and others equally simple, that I am convinced of the existence of a God, and not by those tissues of dry and metaphysical ideas which are better calculated to give to truth an air of falsity than to unveil it. XXI I open the pages of a celebrated professor 1 and I read: ct Atheists, I concede to you that move- ment is essential to matter ; what conclusion do you draw from that ? That the world is the result of a fortuitous concourse of atoms ? You might as well tell me that Homer's Iliad or Voltaire's Henriade is the result of a fortuitous concourse of written characters." I should be very sorry to use that argument to an atheist ; he would make quick work of the comparison. According to laws of the analysis of chances (he would say) I ought not 1 Briere in his edition says that Rivard, who was then professor of philosophy, is here meant, but the argument which follows is a well- known one. (A) PHILOSOPHIC THOUGHTS 39 to be surprised that a thing happens, when it is possible and the difficulty of the result is compen- sated by the number of throws. There is a certain number of throws in which I would back myself to bring 100,000 sixes at once with 100,000 dice. Whatever the definite number of letters with which I am invited fortuitously to create the Iliad^ there is a certain definite number of throws which would make the venture advantageous to me ; indeed, my advantage would be infinite if the number of throws permitted me were infinite. You grant me that matter exists from all eternity and that movement is essential to it. In return for this concession, I will suppose, as you do, that the world has no limits, that the multitude of atoms is infinite, and that this order which causes you astonishment nowhere contradicts itself. Well, from these mutual admis- sions there follows nothing else unless it be that the possibility of fortuitously creating the universe is very small but that the quantity of throws is infinite ; that is to say, that the difficulty of the result is more than sufficiently compensated by the multitude of throws. Therefore, if anything ought to be repugnant to reason, it is the supposition that matter being in motion from all eternity, and there being perhaps in the infinite number of pos- sible combinations an infinite number of admirable arrangements, none of these admirable arrange- ments would have ensued, out of the infinite multitude of those which matter took on succes- sively. Therefore the mind ought to be more 40 DID E ROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS astonished at the hypothetical duration of chaos than at the actual birth of the universe. XXII I divide atheists into three classes. There are some who tell you openly there is no God, and are convinced of this ; these are genuine atheists : there is a fairly large number of people who do not know what to think and would be glad to decide the question by tossing up ; these are sceptical atheists : and a still larger number who \vish there were no God, and who pretend to be convinced of his non- existence and live in harmony with this conviction ; these are the braggadocios of the party. I detest braggarts ; they are dishonest : I pity genuine atheists ; all consolation is dead to them : and I pray God for the sceptics ; they lack knowledge. XXIII The deist maintains the existence of God, the immortality of the soul and its consequences ; the sceptic has not decided on these points ; the atheist denies them. The sceptic, therefore, has one more motive for practising virtue than the atheist, and less than the deist. If it were not for fear of the laws, the natural tendency of a man's character,' and the knowledge of the actual benefits of virtue, the probity of the atheist would be lacking in founda- tion, and that of the sceptic would be built upon a "perhaps/ 7 PHILOSOPHIC THOUGHTS 41 XXIV Scepticism does not suit everybody. It supposes a profound and careful examination. He who doubts because he is not acquainted with the grounds of credibility is no better than an ignor- amus. The true sceptic has counted and weighed his reasons. But it is no easy matter to weigh arguments. Which of us knows their value with any exactness? Out of a hundred proofs of the same truth, each one will have its partisans. Every mind has its own telescope. An objection which is invisible to you is a colossus to my eyes, and you find an argument trivial that to me is crushing in its efficacy. If we dispute about their intrinsic value, how shall we agree upon their relative? Tell me how many moral proofs are needed to balance a metaphysical conclusion? Are my spectacles in fault, or yours? If, then, it is so difficult to weigh reasons, and if there are no questions which have not two sides, and nearly always in equal measure, how come we to cut knots with such rapidity ? How do we come by this convinced and dogmatic air? Have we not a hundred times experienced how revolting is dogmatic presumption? "I have been brought to detest probabilities," says the author of the Essays?- " when they are foisted on me as infallible ; I love words which soften and moderate the temerity of our propositions, per- adventure, in no wise, some people say, met /links, e, book iii, cb. xi. 42 D IDE ROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS and the like ; and if I had to teach children I should so train them to answer in this hesitating and un- decided manner : ' What does that mean ? I do not understand; maybe; is it true?' that they would have the appearance of apprentices at sixty years of age, rather than of doctors at ten, as at present. " XXV What is God ? A question we ask children, and that philosophers have much trouble in answering. We know the age when a child ought to learn to read, to sing, to dance, to begin Latin or geometry. It is only in religion that we take no account of his capacity. He hardly hears what you say before he is asked, "What is God?" It is at the same moment, and from the same lips, that he learns of ' the existence of ghosts, goblins, were-wolves and a God ! He is taught one of the most important truths in a manner adapted to bring it into disrepute one day before the bar of reason.. Would it be at all surprising if, at twenty years of age, finding the existence of God confounded in his mind with a host of idle prejudices, he were to treat it as our judges treat an honest fellow who has fallen into bad company by some accident ? XXVI People begin to speak to us of God too soon, and another mistake is that his presence is not sufficiently insisted upon. Men have banished God PHILOSOPHIC THOUGHTS 43 from their company and have hidden him in a sanctuary ; the walls of a temple shut him in, he has no existence beyond. Fools that you are, break down these limitations that hamper your ideas ; set God free ; see him everywhere, as he is everywhere, or say that he is non-existent. If I had a child to bring up, I would make his God his companion in such a real sense that he would perhaps find it less difficult to become an atheist, than to escape his presence. Instead of confront- ing him with a fellow-man (whom maybe he knows to be worse than himself) I would say outright : " God hears you and you are lying." Young people are influenced by their senses. I would multiply about him symbols indicating the divine presence. If there were a gathering at my house, I would leave a place for God, and I would accustom him to say : * We were four God, my friend, my tutor, and myself." XXVII Ignorance and incuriosity are two soft pillows, but to find them so we must have a head as well contrived as Montaigne's. 1 XXVIII Vigorous minds and ardent imaginations do not take kindly to the indolence of scepticism. They would rather risk a choice than make none ; be deceived than live in doubt. Whether they do not 1 " Oh, que c'est un doulx et mol chevet, et sain, que I'ignorance et rincuriosite, & reposer une teste Hen faicte," Essais, Hv. iii, ch. xiii. 44 DIDEROT S PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS trust their arms, or whether they fear deep waters, we see them always clinging to branches they know to be fragile. They would rather be caught on these branches than abandon themselves to the torrent. They are sure of everything, though they have investigated nothing carefully ; they question nothing because they have neither the patience nor the courage. They make their way by broken lights, and if by chance they come across the truth, it is not by searching, but suddenly and, as it were, by revelation. They are among the dogmatic group what the illuminati are among the pietists. I have seen individuals of this restless type, who could not conceive how tranquillity of mind could be allied with scepticism. "How can one live happily without knowing what one is, whence one comes, whither one goes, why we are here ? " "I make a point of my ignorance on all these questions, and am not distressed, " replies the sceptic coolly ; t c it is not my fault if my reason is mute when questioned on my state. All my life I shall live in ignorance of what it is impossible for me to know, and be none the worse for it. Why should I regret knowledge which I could not attain, and which is doubtless unnecessary to me, since I have it not? I would as soon make myself wretched, says one of the greatest geniuses 1 of our age, because I am not equipped with four eyes, four feet, and two wings." 1 Voltaire. PHILOSOPHIC THOUGHTS 45 XXIX A search for truth should be required of one, but not its attainment. May not a sophism affect me as deeply as a solid proof? I am obliged to admit the falsehood that I take to be the truth, and to reject the truth that I take for a falsehood ; but how am I to blame, if I am deceived from no fault of mine? We are not rewarded in the next world for using our intelligence in this ; ought we to be punished for a lack of it ? To damn a man for foolish reason- ing is to forget that he is a fool, and to treat him as a criminal. XXX What is a sceptic ? A philosopher who has questioned all he believes, and who believes what a legitimate use of his reason and his senses has proved to him to be true. Do you want a more precise definition ? Make a Pyrrhonist sincere, and you have the sceptic. XXXI What has never been put in question has not been demonstrated. What people have not examined without prepossession has never been examined thoroughly. Scepticism is thus the first step to- wards truth. It must be applied generally, for it is the touchstone. If to ascertain the existence of God the philosopher begins by questioning it, is there any proposition which should not be so tested ? 46 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS XXXII Incredulity is sometimes the vice of a fool, and credulity the defect of a man of intelligence. The latter sees far into the immense ocean of possibilities, the former scarcely sees anything possible but the actual. Perhaps this is what produces the timidity of the one, the temerity of the other. XXXIII It is as hazardous to believe too much as too little. The danger of being a polytheist is neither greater nor less than the danger of being an atheist ; now scepticism is the only defence, in any period and in any place, against these two opposite extremes. XXXIV A half-hearted scepticism is the mark of a feeble understanding which reveals a pusillanimous reasoner who permits himself to be alarmed by consequences, a superstitious creature who thinks to honour God by imposing fetters on his reason, a species of un- believer who is afraid of unmasking himself to him- self. For if truth has nothing to lose by examination, as is the demi-sceptic's conviction, what does he think in the bottom of his heart of those privileged notions which he fears to investigate, and which are hidden in a recess of his brain, as in a sanctuary which he dares not approach ? PHILOSOPHIC THOUGHTS 47 XXXV I hear cries against impiety on every side. The Christian is impious in Asia, the Mussulman in Europe, the papist in London, the Calvinist in Paris, the Jansenist at the top of the rue St Jacques, the Molinist at the bottom of the faubourg St M6dard. What is an impious person, then ? Either everybody, or nobody, XXXVI When the pious declaim against scepticism, it seems to me that they either do not understand their own interest, or are inconsistent. If it is certain that a true faith, to be embraced, and a false faith, to be abandoned, need only be fully known, surely it must be highly desirable that universal doubt should spread over the surface of the earth, and that every race should consent to the examination of the truth of its religion. Our missionaries would find a good half of their work already accomplished. XXXVII He who does not deliberately embrace the faith in which he has been bred can no more plume him- self on being a Christian or a Mussulman than upon not being born blind or lame. It is his luck, not his merit. XXXVIII He who would die for a faith whose falsity he was aware of, would be a madman. He who dies 48 DIDEROT S PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS for a false faith, which he thinks a true one, or for a true faith of whose truth he has not been con- vinced by proofs, is a fanatic. The true martyr is he who dies for a true faith, whose truth has been clearly proved to him. XXXI X The true martyr waits for death, the enthusiast rushes towards it. XL He who at Mecca would insult the ashes of Mahomet, overturn his altars and disturb a mosque, would be certainly impaled and perhaps would not be canonised. Such zeal is not now in fashion. Polyeucte in our days would be a madman. XLI The age of revelations, of prodigies, and of extra- ordinary missions is no more. Christianity has no longer need of this scaffolding. A man who took it into his head to play the part of Jonah amongst us, and rushed about the streets crying, "In three days Paris will be no more. Parisians, repent, cover yourselves with sackcloth and ashes, or in three days you will perish," would be seized at once, and taken before a judge, who would certainly send him to the lunatic asylum. It would be no use his saying to us, " Does God love you less than the men of Nineveh : are you less guilty ? " No one would waste his time in answering him, nor would PHILOSOPHIC THOUGHTS 49 wait until the date of his prophecy expired before treating him as a visionary. Elijah may return from the other world when he pleases ; men are such that it would be a miracle indeed if he were well received in this. XLII When a dogma which contradicts the dominant religion, or some event which is inconsistent with the tranquillity of the public, is announced, even if the mission is justified by miracles, the government does well in dealing rigorously, and the people in crying "Crucify." How dangerous to abandon the people to the seductions of an impostor, or the dreams of a visionary ! If the blood of Jesus Christ cried for vengeance against the Jews, 'tis because in shedding it they turned a deaf ear to Moses and the Prophets who foretold the Messiah. If an angel came down from heaven and supported his argu- ments by miracles, and yet preached against the law of Christ, Paul would call him anathema. It is not, therefore, by miracles that a man's mission is to be judged, but by the conformity of his doctrine with that of the people to whom he declares himself sent, especially when the doctrine of that people is proved to be true. XLIII Every innovation in a government is to be feared. The holiest and best of religions, even Christianity, did not make its way without causing some dis- 4 50 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORK$ turbances. The first sons of the Church more thar once exceeded the limits of the patience and modera- tion recommended to them. Let me here quote some fragments of an edict of the Emperor Julian which are very characteristic of the genius of that philosophic prince and of the humours of the zealots of that day. " I had imagined," says Julian, "that the leaders of the Galileans would be sensible of the difference between my methods and those of my predecessor, and that they would be grateful. Under his reign they suffered exile and imprisonment and a number of those they called heretics were put to the sword. Under my reign the exiles were recalled, the prisoners released, and the proscribed given again the possession of their goods. But such is the restless- ness and fury of this sect that since they have lost the privilege of mutual destruction, of tormenting those who are attached to their belief and those who belong to the religion authorised by the laws, they spare no effort and let pass no occasion to stir up revolt. They are people without regard for true piety and without respect for our ordin- ances. . . . Yet we do not drag them to our altars, nor do them violence. ... As to the poorer classes, it seems that they are stirred to sedition by their leaders, who are enraged at the limits we have set to their powers ; for we have excluded them from our courts of law, and they have no longer the power to make away with wills and supplant the legitimate heirs, and take possession of inheritances. . . . That is why we forbid the PHILOSOPHIC THOUGHTS 51 people to assemble factiously and to intrigue at the homes of its seditious priests. . . . Let this edict strengthen the hands of our magistrates who have been more than once insulted by these insurgents, and ran the risk of being stoned. Let them meet peaceably at their leaders, and pray there, let them there receive instruction and conform to their religion ; we permit this so long as they refrain from all sedition. If their meetings are an oppor- tunity for revolt and faction, they and their property will suffer, I warn them. Unbelievers, live in peace . . . and you who have remained faithful to the religion of your country and the gods of your fathers, do not persecute your fellow-men, your fellow- citizens, who are rather to be pitied for their ignorance than blamed for their wickedness. It is by reason and not by violence that men should be brought to the truth. We enjoin therefore upon you all, our faithful subjects, to leave the Galileans in peace." Such were the sentiments of this prince who can be accused of paganism, but not of apostasy. He passed the early years of his life under different masters and in different schools, and made an unhappy choice in later life. He unfortunately decided in favour of the faith of his ancestors and the gods of his country. XLIV I am astonished that the works of this learned Emperor have been preserved to us. They contain passages which, though they do not affect the truth 52 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS of Christianity, are by no means complimentary to certain Christians of his time, and the Fathers of the Church paid the works of their enemies the singular attention of suppressing them. It is apparently from his predecessors that Gregory the Great derived the barbarous zeal against art and letters which inflamed him. If this Pontiff had had his way we should be in the plight of the Mahometans, who have only the Koran to read. What would have been the fate of the writers of antiquity at the hands of a man who committed solecisms from religious motives, who thought that to observe grammatical rules was to set Jesus Christ below Donatus, 1 and who thought himself obliged to complete the ruins of antiquity ? XLV The divinity of the Holy Scriptures is not, how- ever, so clearly apparent therein, that the authority of the sacred historians is completely independent of the testimony of profane authors. Where should we be, if we had to find the finger of God in the literary form of our Bible? What sorry stuff is the Latin translation ! And even the originals are not exactly masterpieces of composition. The prophets, apostles and evangelists wrote as they pleased. If we were permitted to regard the history of the Jews purely as a production of the human mind, Moses and his continuators are no rivals of Livy, Sallust, Caesar, and Josephus, who 1 A Laiin giammarian. PHILOSOPHIC THOUGHTS 53 are not suspected of being inspired. Is not the Jesuit Berruyer preferred to Moses? In our churches there are preserved pictures which we are assured are the work of angels and of the Deity himself. If these pictures were actually the work of Le Sueur or Le Brun, what could I find to say against this immemorial tradition ? Perhaps nothing at all. But when I look at these celestial works, and see the rules of painting violated at every moment both in design and execution, and the truth of art everywhere absent, since I cannot suppose the author an ignoramus, I must accuse the tradi- tion of falsity. I might make use of this analogy between these pictures and Holy Writ, if I were not well aware that it is immaterial whether their con- tents are well or ill written. The prophets' forte was telling the truth, not elegant composition. The Apostles died for the truth of what they preached and wrote, and for nothing else. But, to return to the matter under discussion, those profane writers should have been preserved who must have harmonised with sacred historians, at any rate upon facts such as the existence and miracles of Christ, the qualities and character of Pontius Pilate, and the deeds and martyrdom of the early Christians. XLVI An entire nation, you will say, witnesses to this fact ; dare you deny it ? Yes, 1 dare, since it is not confirmed by the authority of someone not of your side, and I do not know whether that person 54 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS is free from fanaticism and delusion. Moreover, if an author of declared impartiality tells me that a chasm opened in the midst "of a city, that the gods when consulted about this event answered that it would close if the most precious possession was thrown into it, and that a brave knight leapt in and that the oracle was fulfilled ; I should be far less inclined to believe him than if he had simply said that a chasm opened, and that considerable time and labour were required to fill it. The less probability a fact has the more does the testimony of history lose its weight. I should make no difficulty in believing a single honest man who should tell me that His Majesty had just won a complete victory over the allies ; but if all Paris were to assure me that a dead man had come to life again at Passy, I should not believe a word of it. That a historian should impose upon us, or that a whole nation should be deluded there is no miracle in that ! XLVII Tarquin proposed to increase the corps of cavalry that Romulus had formed. An augur declared all change in the army sacrilegious, unless authorised by the gods. Angered at the opposition of the priest and determined to make an end of him and of an art which opposed his will, Tarquin had him summoned to the market-place, and said to him, "Soothsayer, is what I am think- ing of possible? If your knowledge is what you PHILOSOPHIC THOUGHTS 55 boast it to be, you will be able to answer me." The augur was not embarrassed, but consulted the birds and made answer: "Yes, Prince, what you propose is possible." Then Tarquin, drawing a razor from beneath his gown and taking a pebble, said to the augur, c ( Come here and cut me this pebble with this razor, for I thought this possible." Navius, for this was the augur's name, turned to the people and said composedly, c * Strike the pebble with the razor, and may 1 be dragged to torture on the spot if it is not immediately divided." People saw, with surprise, the hardness of the pebble yield to the blade ; it was divided so promptly that the razor reached Tarquin's hand and drew blood. The astonished people applauded, and Tarquin re- nounced his scheme, and declared himself the protector of augurs. The razor and the fragments of the pebble were buried beneath an altar. A statue was put up to the augur, which was still in existence in the reign of Augustus, and both sacred and profane writers bear witness to the truth of this event, in the writings of Lactantius, Dionysius of Halicarnassus, and Saint Augustine. You have heard the story ; now for superstition. c c What do you say to that ? " says the superstitious Quintus to his brother Cicero. " You must either admit it as a fact, or take refuge in a monstrous Pyrrhonism, treat nations and historians as fools, and burn their annals. Will you deny everything rather than allow that the gods interfere in our affairs ? " Hoc ego philosophi non arbitror testibus uti, qui 56 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS aut casu veri aut malitia falsi fictique esse possztnt. Argumentis et rationibus oportet ; quare quidquid ita sit docere, non eventis^ Us prasertim quibus mihi nonliceat y credere. . . . OmitteigiturlituumRomuli, quern in maximo incendio negas potuisse combiiri ? Contemne cot em Accii Navii ? Nihil debet esse in philosophia commentitiis fabellis loci. Illud erat p kilo sop hi totius augurii primum natitram ipsam vide re ^ deinde inventionem^ deinde constantiam. . . . Habent Etrusci exaratumpuerum ait ct or em discipline sues. Nos Quern ? Acciumne Navium ? . . . Placet igitur humanitatis expertes habere Divinitatis auc- tores ? (Cicero, De divinat. , lib. ii, cap. Ixxx, Ixxxi). But kings, peoples, nations, and the whole world believe it. Quasi vere quidquam sit tarn valde quam nihil sapere vulgare ? Aut quasi tibi ipsi in fudicando placeat multitudo}- This is the philo- sopher's reply. Tell me a single prodigy to which it does not apply. The Fathers of the Church, who doubtless found it exceedingly inconvenient to follow Cicero's principles, have preferred to accept Tarquin's adventure, and attribute the art of Navius to the Devil. A very convenient invention, the Devil. 1 et I think a philosopher ought not to rely on evidence which either by accident or design may be false or deceptive. He ought to explain by argument and reasoning why each circumstance happens as it does, rather than by events, especially when they are such as I am unable to credit Let us therefore dispose of Roraulus's staff, which you say resisted the action of the hottest fire, and make light of Navius* flint. There should be no place in philosophy for such fabrications. A phil- osopher ought to look into the whole matter of augury and its origin. The Etruscans set up a boy turned up by a ploughshare as the author of their discipline. Whom have we? Accius Navius ?" . . . "What is commoner than the ignorance of the multitude ? Do you yourself trust the common herd in a judicial case ? " PHILOSOPHIC THOUGHTS 57 XL VI 1 1 Every nation has stories like this, which would be miraculous if true ; which are never proved, but which serve to prove everything ; which it were impious to deny, and folly to believe. XLIX Romulus, struck by lightning, or murdered by the senators, disappeared from Rome. The people and the soldiers murmured, the orders of the state rose one against the other, and Rome in its infancy, divided against itself and surrounded by enemies, stood on the edge of a precipice, when a certain Proculeius came forward gravely, and said : " Romans, this prince whom you regret is not dead: he has ascended to heaven, where he sits at the right hand of Jupiter. 'Go, 'he said to me, 'and calm your fellow-citizens ; tell them that Romulus is with the gods and assure them of my protection ; let them know that the forces of their enemies shall never prevail against them ; their destiny is to be one day the lords of the earth. Let them hand down this prediction from age to age, and to their most distant posterity.' " Some circumstances favour imposture ; and if we consider the state of things in Rome at that time, we shall agree that Proculeius was a man of intelligence and that he chose his time well. He introduced into their minds a feeling which was not without its effect in determining the future greatness of his country. Minim est quantum illi 58 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS vzro h&c nuntianti fidei fuerit ; quamque desiderium Romuli apud plebem fact a fida immortalitatis ', lenitum sit. Famam hanc admiratio viri et pavor pr&sens nobilitavit ; deinde a paucis initio facto, Deum, Deo natum salvere universi Romulumjubent. 1 That Is to say, the people believed in this appari- tion ; the senators pretended to believe, and Romulus had altars raised to him. But this was not all. Soon it was not only to a single individual that Romulus appeared ; he showed himself to more than a thousand people in a single day. He had not been struck by lightning, the senators had not made away with him during a storm, but he had ascended to heaven in the midst of lightnings and thunders in the sight of the people ; and this story became encrusted after a time with such a quantity of additions that the thinkers of the following cen- tury must have found them highly inconvenient. A single proof is more conclusive to me than fifty occurrences. Thanks to the great confidence I have in my reason, my faith is not at the mercy of the first juggler I meet with. Priest of Mahomet, you may cure the lame, make the dumb speak, give sight to the blind, cure the palsied, and raise the dead, nay, even restore to the mutilated the limbs 1 ["It was strange how the man who announced these tidings was believed, and how the people's longing for Romulus was appeased when they believed in his immortality. Admiration of the hero, and terror, added lustre to the story ; then, little by little, Romulus is hailed as god, and the son of a god, by all."] PHILOSOPHIC THOUGHTS 59 they have lost (a miracle hitherto unattempted), and to your great surprise my faith will not be shaken. Do you wish me to become your proselyte ? Then leave these prodigies and let us reason. I trust my judgment more than my eyes. If the religion that you announce to me is true, its truth can be demonstrated by unanswerable arguments. Find these arguments. Why pursue me with prodigies, when a syllogism serves to con- vince me ? Do you find it easier to make a cripple stand upright than to enlighten me ? LI A man lies on the ground, without feeling, without warmth and without movement. They turn him over and over, shake him, burn him, and nothing stirs him. A red-hot iron does not draw from him any sign of life. Is he dead ? No. He is the priest of Calama, qui quando ei placebat ad imitatas quasi lamentantis hominis voces^ ita se auferebat a sensibus et jacebat simillimus mottuo, ut non solum vellicantes atqite pungentes minime sentiret, sed aliquando etiam igne uretur admoto y sine ullo doloris sensu nisi post modum exmilnere* If certain people had found such a case in our times, they would have made a fine use of him ; we should have seen a corpse revived on the ashes of one of the 1 ** Who, when he pleased, became remote from all feeling and lay like a corpse, so that he did not feel those who pinched and pricked him, and was even quite insensible to being burnt by fire, except for the after effect," -t Augustine, Civit^ Dei^ lib, xiv, ch. xxiv. 60 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS elect, and the collection of a Jansenist magistrate 1 would have included a resurrection, and the supporters of the famous constitution 2 would perhaps have been put to confusion. LII . We must admit, says the logician 3 of Port-Royal, that Saint Augustine was right in maintaining, with Plato, that our judgment of truth and our criterion for discerning it belong not to the senses but to the mind : non est veritatis judidum in sensibus. And even the degree of certainty we can obtain through the senses is not very extensive. There are many things which we think we learn through their medium and of which we have not a full assurance. When, therefore, the evidence of the senses is inconsistent with, or does not outweigh, the authority of reason, we have no choice ; logically, we must decide for reason. LIII A certain street 4 resounds with acclamations ; the ashes of one of the elect 5 work more miracles 1 La V^ritt des miracles optrts par ^intercession de M. de Pdris, dtmontrte centre df. UarchevSquc de Sens. Outrage dtdit au Roy par M. de Montgeron. Utrecht, 1737. There was a continuation in 1741 and in 1748. (A) 2 [I.e. the constitution or Bull Unigenitus, which Louis XIV obtained from Clement XI in 1713. It was an anti-Jansenist measure, and was made a law of the land in 1730.] 3 Arnaud and Nicole, in their La Logique^ ou Fart depenser^ Amster- dam, 1675. (Br) 4 The faubourg St Marcel, in which stands the Church of St M&iard. -(A) 8 The Deacon Paris, upon whose tomb the convulsionaries came for cures which Carre de Montgeron collected, and which the Jesuits denied more passionately and obstinately than the philosophers. (A) PHILOSOPHIC THOUGHTS 61 in one day than Jesus Christ during his whole life. Men run, or are carried thither, and I follow the multitude. I am no sooner arrived than I hear cries of <( A miracle, a miracle!" I come nearer, and looking about I see a little cripple * who walks with the aid of three or four charitable persons who hold him up ; and the people, in astonishment, cry out on a miracle. Fools, where is the miracle? Do you not see the rogue has but changed his crutches? It is the same story with miracles as with spirits. I would wager that all who have seen spirits are afraid of them beforehand, and that all those who saw miracles there had made up their minds to see them. LIV We have a vast collection 2 of these so-called miracles which may bid defiance to the most determined incredulity. The author is a senator, a serious man who made profession of a not very intelligent materialism, but who had nothing to gain by his conversion. 3 An eye-witness of the events 1 Cripples are of all sick folk the most readily subject to miraculous influence, if we are to judge by the enormous number of crutches which fill sanctuaries sacred to miraculous cures. In the text the Abbe Becheran may be the person referred to ; bat he leaped like a carp, a detail which Diderot does not give : or Philippe Sergent, stricken by a total paralysis of the right leg and thigh, and by almost complete paralysis of the right arm and hand ; affected by anchylosis of the knee ; affected by a continual tremor in the left side ; and afflicted by imperfect sight so that he was only able to see objects dimly, who was cured in a single moment of all his maladies at the tomb of the Deacon Paris on July loth, 1731. (A) 3 The collection of Montgeron referred to in note I, page 60. 3 Montgeron, who makes this confession, had^been suddenly converted at St Medard, and his conversion is the first miracle he records. (A) 62 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS which he relates, and which he had the opportunity of examining without prejudice or bias, his evidence is accompanied by that of thousands of others. All say that they have seen> and their depositions are as authentic as possible ; the original documents are preserved in the public archives. What is to be said? Simply that these miracles prove nothing, so long as the question of his bona fides is not decided. LV Every argument which is used by two opposing factions cuts both ways. If fanaticism has its martyrs like true religion, and if there have been fanatics among those who died for the true faith, we must either count up (if we can) the number of dead of each camp, and believe ; or look for other ' grounds of credibility. LVI Nothing is more apt to confirm men in their irreligion than false inducements to conversion. Every day unbelievers are told : " Who are you to attack a religion that men such as Paul, Tertullian, Athanasius, Chrysostom, Augustine, Cyprian, and a host of illustrious persons so courageoualy defended? Doubtless you have observed some difficulty which has escaped these great geniuses ; show that you know more than they, or else, if you admit that they are the wiser, submit your doubts to their verdict." This is a frivolous argument. PHILOSOPHIC THOUGHTS 63 The knowledge of its priests is no proof of the truth of a religion. What faith was more absurd than the Egyptians? And what priesthood was more enlightened? " No, I cannot worship this onion ; in what is it superior to other vegetables ? I should be mad indeed to bow down before objects destined for my nourishment ! A strange divinity, a plant that I water, and which grows and dies in my kitchen garden." "Silence, you wretch, your blasphemies nil me with horror. Who are you to argue ? Do you know more than the sacred college ? Who are you to attack the gods, and preach wisdom to their ministers ? Are you wiser than the oracles that the whole world comes to question ? Whatever your answer, I shall be amazed at your pride and temerity ! " .Will Christians never know their strength, and will they never abandon such unhappy sophisms to those who have no better argument? Omittamur ista communia qu& ex utraque parte did possunt) quanqtiam vere ex utraque parte did non possint.' 1 Example, prodigies and authority may make dupes or hypocrites; reason alone can make believers. LVII People agree that it is of the first importance to employ none but solid arguments for the defence of a faith ; yet they would gladly persecute those who attempt to cry down bad arguments. * What, then, is it not enough to be a Christian ? Am I also to 1 [" Let us leave all these common arguments which may be used by either party, although really they cannot be used by either/*] 64 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS be a Christian upon mistaken grounds ? Zealots, I give you fair \varning, I am not a Christian because Saint Augustine was, but because it is reason- able to be one. LVIII I know the zealots well, and they are quick to take alarm. If they once make up their minds that this work contains something repugnant to their ideas, I shall expect all the calumnies they have spread about a hundred better men than myself. If they only call me a deist and a wretch, I shall get off lightly. They have long since damned Descartes, Montaigne, Locke and Bayle ; and I hope that they will damn many others. I tell them that I do not pretend to be a better man nor a better Christian than most of these philosophers. I was born in the Roman, Catholic, and Apostolic Church, and I whole-heartedly submit to its decisions. I wish to die in the faith of my fathers, and I respect it as far as is possible for a man who has never held immediate intercourse with the Deity, and has never witnessed a miracle. That is my confession of faith, and I am persuaded that they will find fault with it, though perhaps not a man among them can make a better. LIX I have occasionally read Abbadie, Huet, 1 and the rest. I arri sufficiently well acquainted with the 1 Abbadie, Traitl de la vtfrtitf de la religion chretienne> 1729. liuet, Traitt philosophique de lafaiblesse de t esprit httmaine, 1723. (A) PHILOSOPHIC THOUGHTS 65 evidences of my religion, and I admit that they are important ; but were they a hundred times more so, Christianity would not be demonstrated to me to be true. Why then demand that I should believe that there are three Persons in one God as firmly as I believe that the three angles of a triangle are together equal to two right angles? Every proof ought to produce in me a certainty proportionate to its collusiveness, and the effect of geometrical, moral and physical proofs upon my mind must be different, or else this distinction is a frivolous one. LX You offer an unbeliever a volume of writings of which you claim to show him the divinity. But before examining your proofs, he will be sure to put some questions about this collection. Has it always been the same ? Why is it less ample now than it was some centuries ago? By what right has this or that work been banished, which another sect reveres ; and this or that work been preserved, which the other has rejected? On what grounds have you preferred this manuscript ? Who guided you in your choice among so many varying copies, which are a proof that these sacred authors have not come down to you In their original purity ? But if the ignorance of copyists or the malice of heretics has corrupted the text, as you will have to admit, you must restore the text to its original condition before you prove its divinity ; for your proofs and my faith cannot rest upon a collection 5 66 DWEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS of mutilated documents. To whom will you entrust this reform ? The Church. But I cannot agree to the infallibility of the Church, until the divinity of the Scriptures is proved. I am therefore reduced to scepticism. Your only answer to all these difficulties is by the confession that the first foundations of the faith are purely human ; that the choice between manu- scripts, the restoration of passages, finally the collection, has been made in accordance with the rules of criticism. Well, I do not refuse the divinity of the sacred books a degree of faith proportioned to the certainty of these rules. LXI It was during my search for proofs that I found difficulties. The books which contain the motives of my belief offer at the same time inducements to unbelief. They are arsenals from which either party may draw weapons. 1 have seen the deist arm himself there against the atheist ; the deist and the atheist attack the Jew ; the atheist, the deist and the Jew combine against the Christian ; the Christian, the deist, the atheist and the Jew oppose the Mussulman ; the atheist, the deist, the Jew, and the Mussulman, and a multitude of Christian sects, attack the Christian ; and the sceptic with his hand against every man. I was the umpire, and held the balance between the adversaries. It rose or fell in sympathy with the weight thrown into the scales. After long hesitation, the balance dipped PHILOSOPHIC THOUGHTS 6; in favour of the Christian, but simply by way of reaction. I can bear witness to my own impartial- ity. I might have made more of this surplus. I call God to witness my sincerity. LXII This diversity of opinions has led the deists to imagine an argument which is perhaps more curious than solid. Cicero, having to prove that the Romans were the most warlike people in the world, skilfully extracts this admission from the lips of their rivals. Gauls, to whom, if any, do you yield the palm in courage? To the Romans. Parthians, after you, who are the bravest of men ? The Romans. Africans, whom would you fear, if you were to fear any? The Romans. Let us, say the deists, interrogate the religionists in a like manner. Chinese, what religion would be the best, if yours were not the best? Naturalism. Mussulmans, what religion would you embrace if you abjured Mahomet? Naturalism. Christians, what is the true religion if it be not Christianity? Judaism. But you, Jews, what is the true religion, if Judaism be false ? Naturalism. Now, those, continues Cicero, to whom the second place is unanimously awarded and who in their turn do not cede the first place to anyone it is those who incontestably deserve that place. LETTER ON THE BLIND FOR THE USE OF THOSE WHO SEE 1 Possunt nee posse videntur. sEneid, lib. v, 23. 2 IT was not more than I suspected, that the blind girl whom Monsieur de Reaumur had couched for cataract would not inform you of what you were anxious to know ; but I little thought it would be neither her fault nor yours. I have in person, and by means of his best friends and by paying him many compliments, applied to her benefactor, but all in vain ; the first dressing will be removed with- out you. Some persons of the highest distinction have had the honour of sharing this refusal with philosophers, and, in a word, he does not wish to remove the veil, except in the presence of some eye- witnesses of no great importance. If you would know why that wonderful operator makes a secret of experiments at which you think too great a number of intelligent witnesses cannot be present, my answer is, that the observations of such a cele- brated person do not so much stand in need of spectators, whilst making, as of hearers when made. 1 The Letter was addressed to Madame de Puisieux. (A) 2 |" The original is : Possunt quia possunt videntur "They succeed because they think they will succeed.* 5 ] 68 THE LETTER ON THE BLIND 69 Thus, disappointed, madam, I have returned to my original intention, and, since I was forced to go without an experiment in which I saw little profit would accrue to you or to me, but of which Monsieur de Reaumur will doubtless make a much better use, I set to work to philosophise with my friends upon the important matter which is the object of it. How happy should I be, if the narrative of one of our conversations might stand instead of the spectacle 1 so rashly promised you ! The day that the Prussian 1 operated on Simoneau's daughter for cataract, we went to have some talk with the Puisaux 2 man who was born blind. He is possessed of good solid sense, is known to great numbers of persons, understands a little chemistry, and has attended the botanical lectures at the Jardin du Roi with some profit to himself. His father was a distinguished professor of philosophy at the Univer- sity of Paris. He had private means, sufficient to have satisfied his remaining senses, but a taste for pleasure led him into some excesses in his youth ; people took advantage of his weaknesses, his affairs became embarrassed, and finally he withdrew to a little town in the provinces, from whence he pays a yearly visit to Paris, bringing with him liqueurs which give great satisfaction. These, madam, are not very philosophic details, but for that very reason are likely to convince you that the person I am speaking of is not imaginary. 1 Hilnier, a Prussian oculist. (Br) 2 A small town in the Gatinais. (D) 70 D IDE ROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS We arrived at our blind man's house about five o'clock in the afternoon, and we found him busy teaching his son to read with raised letters. He had only been up an hour, for I must tell you the day begins for him when it is ending for us. His custom is to look after his household affairs and to work while others are asleep. At midnight nothing interrupts him, and he is in no one's way. His first care is to set in its place everything that has been displaced during the day, and when his wife wakes she generally finds the house tidy. The difficulty the blind have in finding things that are mislaid makes them orderly, and I have observed that their intimates also share this quality, either from the effect of the good example of the blind, or from a feeling of compassion towards them. How unhappy would the blind be without the little attentions of those about them ! nay, we ourselves feel the want of them. Great services are like the large gold or silver coins that we rarely make use of, but small attentions are small change which is always passing from hand to hand. This blind man is a good judge of symmetry. Symmetry, which is perhaps a matter of pure con- vention among us, is certainly so in many respects between a blind man and the sighted. A blind man studies by his touch that disposition required between the parts of a whole to enable it to be called beautiful ; and then at length attains to a just application of that term. But in saying "that is beautiful," he does not form an opinion, it is no THE LETTER ON THE BLIND 71 more than repeating the judgment of those who see ; and is not this the case of three-fourths of those who give their opinion on a play or a book ? Beauty for the blind is but a word when divorced from utility, and, wanting an organ, how many things are there the utility of which escapes them ? Are not the blind very much to be pitied in accounting nothing beautiful unless it be likewise good ? How many admirable things are lost to them ! The only compensation for their loss is that their ideas of beauty, though less extensive, are more definite than those of many keen-sighted philosophers who have written prolix treatises on the subject. This blind man often speaks of mirrors. You think he does not know the meaning of the word, yet he is never known to put a glass in a wrong light He speaks as sensibly as we on the qualities and defects of the organ which he lacks. If he attaches no idea to the terms he makes use of, yet he has the advantage over most other men that he never uses them wrongly. He speaks so wisely and so well of so many things absolutely unknown to him, that his conversation would considerably lessen the weight of that inference which, without knowing wherefore, we all draw from what passes in ourselves to what passes within the minds of others. I asked him what he meant by a mirror ? * c An instrument," answered he, "which sets things in relief at a distance from themselves, when properly placed with regard to it. It is like my hand, which, to feel an object, I must not put on one side of it," 72 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS Had Descartes been born blind, he might, I think, have hugged himself for such a definition. Pray consider what an ingenious combination of ideas it implies. This blind man's only knowledge of objects is by touch. He knows by hearing other men say so that they know objects by sight as he knows them by touch ; at any rate that is the only idea he can form of the process. He also knows that we cannot see our own face though we can touch it. Sight, he therefore concludes, is a kind of touch which extends to distant objects and is not applied to our face. Touch gives him an idea only of relief. Therefore, he concludes, a mirror is an instrument that represents us in relief outside ourselves. How many famous philosophers have laboured with less subtlety to arrive at conclusions equally erroneous ! But if a mirror astonished our blind man, how much greater was his surprise when we told him that there are instruments which magnify objects, while others remove them without duplicating them, put them out of their place, bring them nearer, remove them farther, and reveal the minutest details to the eyes of naturalists ; while others again multiply objects a thousand times, and others appear to change the figure of objects completely. He asked us a hundred curious questions concerning these phenomena. For instance, he asked us if only persons who were called naturalists could see with the microscope, and if only astronomers could see with the telescope ; if the instrument for enlarging objects were bigger than that for diminishing them ; if that which brings THE LETTER ON THE BLIND 73 them nearer were shorter than that for removing them farther off. But what puzzled him was that the other self, which according to him the mirror represents in relief, should not be tactile. "So this little instrument," said he, "sets two senses to contradict one another ; a more perfect instrument would perhaps reconcile these contradic- tions, without the object being ever more real for that, and perhaps a third instrument, still more perfect and less illusory, would cause these contra- dictions to disappear and show us our error. "" "And what are eyes, do you suppose?" asked Monsieur de . "An organ," replied the blind man, Cf on which the air has the effect this stick has on my hand." That answer amazed us, and while we gazed at one another in astonishment he con- tinued : ' ' When I place my hand between your eyes and an object, my hand is present to you but the object is absent. The same thing happens when I reach for one thing with my stick and come across another." Madam, only turn to Descartes 1 Dioptrics, and there you will see the phenomena of sight illus- trated by those of touch, and the plates full of men busied in seeing with sticks. Descartes, and all the later writers, have not been able to give us clearer ideas of vision ; and that great philosopher was, in this respect, no more superior to the blind man than a common man who has the use of his eyes. No one thought of asking him questions as to 74 DIDEROT 'S PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS FIG. i. The above figure is an enlarged reproduction of the cut in the original edition of the Letter 071 the Blind. In the Discattrs de la mttkodC) plus la dioptrique^ les mtttoreS) la mtcanisme et la musique (Leyden, 1637), blind people trying to see with sticks are often repeated, but these are small figures only an inch in height dressed as beggars and accompanied by a dog. Diderot probably refers to an edition by P. N. Poisson of this work (1724). (A) THE LETTER ON THE BLIND 75 painting and writing, but it is obvious that his comparison would fit in with every question, and I make no doubt but that he would have told us that to try to read or to see without eyes was like looking for a pin with a thick stick. We only talked to him about those kinds of glasses which exhibit objects in relief, and which are both so very similar to and so very different from mirrors ; but these we perceived rather contradicted than coincided with his idea of a looking-glass, and he was apt to think that a painter might perhaps paint a looking-glass, and thus it came to represent objects in colours. We saw him thread very fine needles. May I ask you, madam, to suspend your reading for a while and try what you would do in his place ? In case you do not light upon any expedient, I will tell you of our blind man's. He takes the eye of the needle transversely between his lips and in the same direc- tion as his mouth, then by his tongue and suction he draws in the thread, which follows his breath unless it is much too thick for the eye ; but in that case a man with sight is in the same difficulty as the blind. He has a surprising memory for sounds, and can distinguish as many differences in voices as we can in faces. He finds in these an infinite number of delicate gradations which escape us because we have not the same interest in observing them. For us, these shades of difference are like our own counten- ance. Of all the men we have seen, the one we least remember is our own self. We notice faces to 76 DIDEROT'S PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS recognise people ; and if we do not remember our own, it is because we are never liable to mistake ourselves for another person or another for our- selves. Moreover, the mutual aid our senses lend stands in the way of their perfection. This will not be the only occasion where I shall have to remark upon this. On this head our blind man said : " That he should think himself a pitiable object in wanting those advantages which we enjoy, and that he should have been inclined to consider us as superior beings had he not a hundred times found us very much inferior to him in other respects." This reflection led to another. This blind man, we said, values himself as much as, and perhaps more than, we who see. Why then, if the brute reasons (and it is scarce to be doubted), why on weighing its advantages over man as better known to it than those of man over it, should it not make a similar inference ? He has arms, perhaps says the gnat, but I have wings. He has weapons, says the lion, but have we not claws? The elephant would look on us as insects ; and all the animals, while allowing us reason, with which we should at the same time stand in great need of their instinct, would claim that with their instinct they could do very well with- out our reason. We have such a strong desire to exaggerate our qualities, and make little of our defects, that it would seem man's part to write a treatise on force, and animals' on reason. One of our company bethought him of asking our THE LETTER ON THE BLIND 77 blind man if he would like to have eyes. "If it were not for curiosity," he replied, " I would just as soon have long arms : it seems to me my hands would tell me more of what goes on in the moon than your eyes or your telescopes ; and besides, eyes cease to see sooner than hands to touch. I would be as well off if I perfected the organ I possess, as if 1 obtained the organ which I am deprived of." Our blind man points with such exactness at the place whence a noise comes that I make no doubt the blind may, by practice, become very dexterous and very dangerous. I will tell you a story which will convince you how imprudent it would be to stand the throwing of a stone or discharging of a pistol by a blind man, were he in the least used to that weapon. He had in his youth a quarrel with one of his brothers, who came off badly. Provoked at some insulting language, he seized the first missile which came to hand, threw it at him, and hit him directly on the forehead, so as to lay him flat on the ground. This, with some other occurrences of the like kind, caused him to be brought before the police. The outward show of power, which affects us so strongly, is as nothing to the blind. Our blind man appeared before the magistrate, as before an equal; menaces did not intimidate him. "What will you do to me?" he asked Monsieur Herault. 1 "I will commit you to a dungeon," answered the magistrate. "Ah, sir," the blind man replied, **I 1 Lieutenant of police. (Br) 78 DIDERO'rS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS have been in one for twenty-five years." There was an answer, madam ; and what a text for one who is so fond of moralising as your humble servant ! We quit life as we would a charming scene, the blind leave it as a dungeon ; and if we have more pleasure in living than he, he has less reluctance to meet his end. The blind man of Puisaux judges of his nearness to the fire by the degrees of heat ; of the fulness of vessels by the sound made by liquids which he pours into them ; of the proximity of bodies by the action of the air on his face. He is so sensitive to the least atmospheric change, that he can distinguish between a street and a closed alley. He is an extremely good judge of the weight of bodies and the capacity of vessels ; and he has trained his arms to be such an exact balance, his fingers to be such skilful compasses, that in this kind of statics I would always back our blind man l against twenty persons with all their eyes about them. The smooth surface of bodies has as many shades of difference for him as the sound of voices, and there is no risk of his mistaking his wife for another, unless he was to be the gainer by the change. Yet it is very probable that among a blind people wives would be in common, or their laws against adultery must be severe indeed, so very easy would it be for wives to deceive their husbands by concerting a sign with their gallants. 1 Clement (dug ann&s Htt^raires, lettre xxxiii) chooses this passage to give his correspondent some idea of this new book of Diderot's which he describes as obscure, and in which he only finds a very slight exhibition of learning. (A) THE LETTER ON THE BLIND 79 He judges of beauty by touch that is easy to understand ; but what is not so easy to grasp is that his judgment is influenced by pronunciation and the sound of a voice. Anatomists ought to tell us if there is any relation between the parts of the mouth and the palate and the exterior conformation of the face. He can turn small articles on the lathe, and do needlework ; he levels with a square ; he puts together and takes to pieces simple machines. He is so far skilled in music as to play a piece when he has been told the notes and their value. He judges of the duration of time much more accurately than we by the succession of actions and of thoughts. A smooth skin, firm flesh, an elegant shape, sweet breath, charm of voice and graceful pronunciation are qualities he prizes very highly. He married to have eyes of his own. Before this, he had an idea of taking a deaf man as his partner, to whom he could lend ears in exchange for eyes. I could not sufficiently wonder at his singular address in a great many things ; and on our expressing our surprise, "I perceive, gentlemen," said he, " that you are not blind : you are astonished at what I do, and why not as much at my speak- ing ? " There is more philosophy, I believe, in this answer of his than he was aware of. The facility with which we are brought to speak is not a little surprising. We have a number of ideas which cannot be represented by sensible objects, and which have no substance, as it were, and we are obliged to find terms for them by making use of a So DIDEROT'S PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS number of ingenious and profound analogies observed between them and the ideas they suggest. Thus a blind man should find greater difficulty in learning to speak because there is a much larger number of imperceptible objects in his world, and thus his field for comparing and combining is much more limited. How, for example, can he rightly use the word expression (of countenance)? It is the same of many things imperceptible to the blind ; and for us who see, it is often found hard to explain very precisely what it is. If it largely resides in the eye, touch will be useless ; and what does a blind man make of dead eyes, or sparkling or expressive eyes? I infer from thence that we unquestionably derive great advantages from the concurrence of our senses and our organs ; still, it would be quite another thing did we use them separately, and never employed two when one would suffice. To add touch to sight, when sight would do the business, is like putting to a carriage with two stout horses a third, which will draw one way while the others draw another. As to me it has always been very clear that the state of our organs and our senses has a great influence on our metaphysics and our morality, and that those ideas which seem purely intellectual are closely dependent on the conformation of our bodies, I put some questions to the blind man about the virtues and vices. The first thing I remarked was his extreme abhorrence of theft ; possibly from two reasons firstly, the facility with THE LETTER ON THE BLIND 81 which people could steal from him unobserved, and secondly (and still more perhaps ), because he could be immediately seen were he to go about filching. Not that he is at any loss to secure himself against that sense which he knows we have above him, or that he is clumsy at hiding what he might steal. Modesty he makes no great account of. If it were not for the weather, against which clothes are a protection, he would hardly understand their use ; and he openly admits he cannot see why one part of the body should be hidden rather than another ; and still less by what caprice some of those parts should be especially singled out, which from their use and the indispositions to which they are subject ought rather to be kept free. Though living in an age when philosophy has rid us of a great number of prejudices, I do not think we shall ever arrive at such complete insensibility to the prerogatives of modesty as this blind man. Diogenes would have been no philosopher in his account. As of all the external signs which raise our pity and ideas of pain the blind are affected only by cries, I have in general no high thought of their humanity. What difference is there to a blind man between a man making water and one bleeding in silence? Do not we ourselves cease to be compassionate when distance or the smallness of the objects produces on us the same effect as deprivation of sight upon the blind ? So much do our virtues depend on the sensations we receive, and the degree by which we are affected by external things. I don't doubt that if it were not 6 82 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS for the fear of punishment, many people would find it less disagreeable to kill a man at a distance at which he would appear no bigger than a swallow, than to cut an ox's throat with their own hands. We pity a horse in pain, and we make nothing of crushing an ant ; and is it not by the same principle that we are moved ? Ah, madam, how different is the mor- ality of the blind from ours ? How different would that of a deaf man likewise be from his ? And to one with a sense more than we have, how deficient would our morality appear to say nothing more ? Our metaphysics and theirs agree no better. How many of their principles are mere absurdities to us, and vice versd ? Concerning this I might enter into details, which I am pretty certain would amuse you, but which certain people, who make a crime of every- thing, would not fail to exclaim against as profanity and infidelity, as if it were in my power to make the blind perceive things otherwise than they do. I will content myself with one observation, which every- one must allow, and that is, that the great argument for the wonders of nature falls flat upon the blind. The facility with which we create (if I may say so) new objects by means of a little glass, is something more incomprehensible to them than the stars which they have been condemned never to see. This luminous globe which moves from east to west sur- prises them less than a small fire which they can increase or diminish at will ; and as they see matter ' in a more abstract manner than we do, they are less indisposed to believe that it thinks. THE LETTER ON THE BLIXD 83 If a man who had had sight only for a day or two found himself in the midst of a blind people, he would either have to hold his peace or be con- sidered a brain-sick fool. Every day lie would come out with some new wonder, which would only be such to them, and which their free-thinkers would oppose tooth and nail. Might not the apolo- gists of religion greatly avail themselves of such a stubborn unbelief, which, however just in some respects, is yet so very ill-founded ? Be pleased to dwell only a little upon this supposition ; it will remind you of the persecutions undergone by those poor wretches who discovered truth in the dark ages and were rash enough to reveal it to their blind contemporaries, and found their bitterest enemies were those who from their circumstances and educa- tion would have seemed most likely to receive it willingly. So much for the morals and metaph\ sics of the blind. I now pass on to less important matters, which have nevertheless lately been the chief subject of observation with regard to the blind ever since the Prussian oculist's arrival. First question : How can a man born blind form ideas of figures? By the movements of his own body and by stretching his hand in various directions, by passing his fingers continuously over an object, he gets an idea oi space. If he passes his fingers along a taut thread, he obtains the idea of a straight line ; if he follows the curve of a slack thread, that of a curve. In a more general sense, by repeated usage of the sense of 84 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS touch, he has a memory of sensations experienced at different points ; and he is capable of combining these sensations or points and forming figures. A straight line for a blind man who is not a geomet- rician is but the memory of a series of sensations of touch upon a taut thread ; a curve, the memory of a series of tactile sensations referred to the surface of some concave or convex solid. In the case of a geometrician, study corrects the idea of these lines by their properties which he discovers. But whether geometrician or no, the man born blind refers every- thing to his fingers' ends. We combine coloured points, he only palpable points, or, to speak more precisely, only such tactile sensations as he remem- bers. He does not go through a mental process analogous to ours ; he does not create an image, for to do this it is necessary to colour a background and mark upon it points of a different colour from that background. Make these points of the same colour as the ground, and they are at once lost in it, and the figure disappears ; at any rate, that is the case in my imagination, and I suppose all imaginations are alike. When I propose to perceive in my head a straight line otherwise than by its properties, I begin by spreading in it a white cloth, against which I set out a series of black points in the like direction. The stronger the colour of the ground and points, the clearer my perception of the points. To view in my imagination a figure of a colour resembling that of the ground, puts me to no less trouble than if out of myself and on a canvas. You see "then, THE LETTER ON THE BUND 85 madam, that laws might be given for imagining with ease various objects variously coloured, but such laws are by no means calculated for one born blind. Such a man who cannot colour (and consequently cannot figure as we understand it) only remembers such sensation as one derives from touch, which he refers to different points, places and distances, and of which he composes figures. I believe that we who see never Imagine any shape without colour- ing it, and that if we are given little balls in the dark, whose substance and colour are unknown to us, we shall immediately think of them as black or white, or some other colour ; and that if we did not, we, like the blind man, should have the remembrance only of little sensations excited at our fingers* ends, and such as little round bodies may occasion. If this remembrance be very fleeting with us, if we have very little idea how one born blind fixes, recalls and combines the sensations of touch, it is owing to the custom we derive from our eyes of realising everything in our imagination by means of colours. It has happened, however, that during the agitations of a violent passion I felt a thrill run through my whole hand, and I felt the im- pression of the bodies I had touched some time ago revived as vividly as if they had been still present to my touch, and I realised very distinctly that the limits of sensation exactly coincided with those of these absent bodies. Although sensation by itself is Indivisible, it occupies, if one may use the word, an extension In space to which the blind man Is 86 DJDEROrS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS able to add and subtract mentally by enlarging or diminishing the parts affected. By this means he compares points, surfaces, and solids ; and he could imagine a solid as large as this terrestrial globe, if he were to imagine his fingers' ends as large as this globe, and occupied by sensation in its , length, breadth, and depth. I know of nothing which is a better proof of the reality of this internal sense than this faculty, weak in us, but strong in those born blind, of feeling or recalling the sensation of bodies when they are absent and no longer acting on us. We cannot make a blind man understand how imagination represents absent objects as present to us, but we can easily recognise in ourselves the faculty that the blind possess of feeling at one's fingers' ends an absent body. To do this, press the forefinger and thumb together, shut your eyes ; separate your fingers, and immediately after this separation examine yourself and tell me if the sensation does not linger after the pressure has ceased ; if, while the pressure lasted, your mind appears to be in your head rather than at the ends of your fingers, and if this pressure does not convey the nature of a surface by the space which the sensation occupies? We only distinguish the presence of external things from their picture in our imagination by the strength or weakness of, the impression ; and similarly, the blind only distinguish the sensation from the actual presence of an object at their fingers' ends, by the strength or weakness of that sensation. THE LETTER ON THE BLIND 8; If ever a philosopher, blind and deaf from his birth, were to construct a man after the fashion of Descartes, I can assure you, madam, that he would put the seat of the soul at the fingers' ends, for thence the greater part of the sensations and all his knowledge are derived. Who is to inform him that his head is the seat of his thoughts? If the labours of the imagination tire our brain, this is because the effort we make to imagine is somewhat similar to that to perceive very near or very small objects. But this would not be the case with a man blind and deaf from his birth, for the sensations which he has gathered from touch will be the world, so to speak, of all his ideas, and I should not be surprised if, after a profound meditation, his fingers were as wearied as our heads. I am not afraid that a philosopher might object to such an one that the nerves cause our sensations and that they all start from the brain. Were these two propositions fully demonstrated, which is very far from being the case, especially the former, an exposition of all the dreams of naturalists on this head would be sufficient to confirm him in his opinion. But if the imagination of the blind mac be no more than the faculty of calling to mind and com- bining sensations of palpable points ; and of a sighted man, the faculty of combining and calling to mind visible or coloured points, the person born blind consequently perceives things in a much more abstract manner than we ; and in questions purely speculative, he is perhaps less liable to be deceived. 88 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS For abstraction consists in separating in thought the perceptible qualities of a body, either from one another, or from the body itself in which they are inherent ; and error arises where this separation is done in a wrong way or at a wrong time in a wrong way in metaphysical questions, or at a wrong time in applied mathematics. There is perhaps one certain method of falling into error in metaphysics, and that is, not sufficiently to simplify the subject under in- vestigation ; and an infallible secret for obtaining incorrect results in applied mathematics is to suppose objects less compounded than they usually are. There is one kind of abstraction of which so few are capable that it seems reserved for purely intel- lectual beings, and that is that by which everything would be reduced to numerical units. We must admit that the results of this geometry would be very exact, and its formulas very comprehensive, for there are no objects, either possible or actually existent, which these simple units could not represent, by points, lines, surfaces, solids, thoughts, ideas, sensations, etc. ; and if this should prove to be the foundation of Pythagoras's doctrine, he might be said to have failed in his aim, his mode of philoso- phising being too much above us, and too near that of the Supreme Being, who, according to the in- genious phrase of an English geometrician, 1 always geomet rises in the universe. 1 [Briere gives the name of this geometrician as Rapson (sic}. Raphson, not a very distinguished mathematician, may, among many others, have quoted this doctrine of Plato, but it is not very important if he did so. What makes the dictum important in Plato's mouth is that he had a THE LETTER ON THE BLIND 89 But units pure and simple are too vague and general symbols for us. Our senses bring us back to symbols more suited to our comprehension and the conformation of our organs. We have arranged that these signs should be common property and serve, as it were, for the staple in the exchange of our ideas. We have made them for our eyes in the alphabet, and for our ears in articulate sounds ; but we have none for the sense of touch, although there is a way of speaking to this sense and of obtaining its responses. For lack of this language, there is no communication between us and those born deaf, blind, and mute. They grow, but they remain in a condition of mental imbecility. Perhaps they would have ideas, if we were to communicate with them in a definite and uniform manner from their infancy ; for instance, if we were to trace on their hands the same letters we trace on paper, and associated always the same meaning with them. Is not this language, madam, as good as another? Is it not ready to hand, and would you dare to say that you have never been communicated with by this method ? Nothing remains but to fix it, and make its grammar and dictionaries, if it is found that the expression by the common characters of writing is too slow for the sense of touch. Know- ledge has three entrances by which it reaches our theory that geometry is more fundamental and comprehensive than arithmetic. He disagreed in this respect from the Pythagoreans because he clearly realised that there were certain lengths of lines expressible geometrically but not arithmetically ; cf. Brunschvicg, Lts Mopes de fa philosophie mathtmatiqtte, pp. 45. 47 4&] 90 DTDRROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS mind, and we keep one barricaded for want of signs. If the two others had been neglected we should now be little better than beasts. Just as a pressure Is the only sign we have to the touch, so a cry would have been the only sign to the hearing. We have to lose one sense before we realise the advantage of symbols given to the remainder, and people who have the misfortune to be born deaf, blind, and mute, or who have lost these three senses by some accident, would be delighted if there existed a clear and precise language of touch. It is much easier to use symbols already invented than to invent them, as one is obliged to do when there are none current. What an advantage it would have been for Saunderson to find an arithmetic arranged with signs for the touch all ready to hand at the age of five, instead of having to invent it at twenty-five ! This Saunderson, madam, is another blind man whose story you will be interested to hear. Wonderful stories, indeed, are told of him, and yet there is not one to which, from his attain- ments in literature and his skill in mathematics, we may not safely give credit. He used the same machine for algebraical calculations and for the description of rectilinear figures. 1 You would be interested in an account of this if intelligible, and you will see my description assumes no more know- ledge on your part than you actually possess, and that it would be very useful to you if you should ever want to make long calculations by touch. 1 See note I, p. 219. THE LETTER OX THE BLIND g\ Imagine a square such as you see in figures 2 and 3, divided into four equal parts by lines perpendicular to the sides, in such a way that it gives nine points, I, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, ;, 8, 9. Suppose this square per- forated with nine holes to hold pins of two kinds, both of the same length and thickness, but one kind with a head larger than that of the other. The large-headed pins are only placed in the centre of the square, the small-headed pins only on the sides, except in the single case of zero. Zero is marked by a large-headed pin placed in the centre of the small square which has no pin set on the sides. The figure I is represented by a small-headed pin, placed in the centre of the square, which has no pin set on its sides. The figure 2, by a large-headed pin placed in the centre of the square, and by a small- headed pin placed in one of the sides at the point I. The figure 3, by a large-headed pin placed in the centre of the square, and by a small-headed pin placed in one of its sides at the point 2. The figure 4, by a large-headed pin placed in the centre of the square, and by a small-headed pin placed in -one of the sides at the point 3. The figure 5, by a large- headed pin placed in the centre of the square, and by a small-headed pin placed in one of the sides at the point 4. The figure 6, by a large-headed pin placed in the centre of the square, and by a small-headed pin placed in one of its sides at the point 5. The figure 7, by a large-headed pin placed in the centre of the square, and by a small-headed pin placed in one of the sides at the point 6. The figure 8, by a large- 92 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS headed pin placed In the centre of the square, and by a small-headed pin placed in one of the sides at the point 7. The figure 9, by a large-headed ...J d FIG. 2. '/ FIG. 3. pin placed in the centre of the square, and by a small-headed pin placed in one of the sides at the point 8. This gives ten different symbols for the sense of touch, each of which corresponds to one of our ten THE LETTER ON THE BLIND 93 arithmetical characters. Now imagine a board as large as you choose, divided into small squares arranged horizontally and separated by a small space one from the other, as you see in fig. 4, and you have Saunderson's instrument You can easily see that there is no number which cannot be expressed in the tablet, and hence no arithmetical process which cannot be carried out therein. Suppose, for example, that we want to find the sum of, or to add, the nine following numbers : I o 3 4 5 2 3 4 5 6 3 4 5 6 7 4 5 6 7 8 5 6 7 8 9 6 7 8 9 7 8 9 i 8 9 o i o 9 o i 2 3 I write them on the table in the order they are named : the first figure on the left of the first number, on the first square to the left of the first line; the second figure on the left of the first number, on the second square on the left of the same line, apd so on. I place the second number in the second row of squares ; units are units, tens are tens, etc. I place the third number in the third row of squares, 94 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS and so on, as you see in fig. 4. Next, touching with my fingers each vertical row from the top to the bottom, beginning with that \\hich is most to FIG. 4. my left, I add together the numbers therein ex- pressed ; and I write the tens that are , over at the end of that column. I pass to the second column, moving leftward, and work in this way ; thence to the third, and so on completing my addition* THE LETTER OX THE BLIND 95 This Is how the same tablet served him to prove the properties of rectilinear figures. Supposing he had to prove that parallelograms which have the FIG. 5. same base and same height are equal in area, he placed his pins as you see in fig. 5 ; he added names to the angles, and proceeded with the proof with his fingers. Supposing that Saunderson only used large- g6 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS headed pins to mark the limits of his fingers, he could arrange round these small-headed pins of nine different varieties with all of which he was familiar. Thus he was never at a loss, except in cases where the great number of angular points which he was obliged to name in his proof forced him to have recourse to the letters of the alphabet. \Ve are not told how he used them. We only know that his fingers moved over his tablet with astonishing rapidity ; that he made the longest calculations successfully ; that he could interrupt them, and recognise when he was in error ; that he could verify them with ease ; and that this work did not take him as much time as one might imagine, because he could arrange his tablet to suit his convenience. This arrangement consisted in placing large- headed pins in the centre of all the squares. This done, he had only to fix their value by small-headed pins, except in the case when he wished to express an unit. In that case he put a small-headed pin in the centre of the square, in place of the large- headed pin. Sometimes, instead of forming a complete line with pins, he only placed them at all the angles or points of intersection, and round these lie stretched silk threads which completed his figures (See fig. 6.) He left sever al other instruments which facilitated his geometrical studies ; the use he made of these is not known, and more acumen would perhaps be NICHOLAS Lucafian To face p. 96. THE LETTER ON THE BL1XD 97 required to discover this than to solve some problem in integral calculus. Let some geometrician tr}~ to discover the function of four pieces of solid wood mu mm mm mm mm mm mm am ms wm mm FIG. 6. iii the form of rectangular parallelopipeds, each 1 1 inches by $^ wide and a little more than half an inch thick, and whose two larger opposite surfaces were divided into small squares similar to the abacus 1 have just described ; but with this differ- 7 98 DWEKOTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS ence, that they were only perforated at certain points, in which pins were driven in up to their head. Each surface had nine small arithmetical FIG. 7. tablets, each with ten numbers, and each ot these ten numbers was composed of ten figures. Fig. 7 represents one of the small tablets, and here are the numbers it contained : THE LETTER OX THE BLIND 99 9 4 o S 4 2 4 i 8 6 4 i 7 9 2 5 4 2 S 4 6 3 9 6 S 7 i 8 8 7 8 s 6 S 8 4 1 o 5 8 8 9 4 6 4 9 4 o ^ o He was the author of an excellent work of Its kind The Elements of Algebra 1 where the only signs of his blindness are the peculiarity of certain demonstrations which a sighted man would probably not have thought of. To him we owe the division of the cube into six equal pyramids whose apex is at the centre of the cube and the base of each is one of its faces. This is used by him as a simple proof that every pyramid is the third of a prism having the same height and the same base. His taste for mathematics, his small means, and the advice of his friends decided him to give public lectures. His marvellous facility for clear demon- stration encouraged his friends to think he would prove a successful teacher, for he taught his pupils as if they could not see, and a blind man who makes 1 Printed in London, a year after Saunderson's death, at the expense of Cambridge University. In 1756 de Joncourt translated it, with some additional remarks (Amsterdam, 2 vols.)- (Br) TOO DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS himself clear to the blind must be doubly lucid to the sighted ; it is a telescope the more. His biographers say that his talk abounded in happy expressions, and I can well believe it. But "What do you mean by happy expressions?" you will perhaps inquire. I answer, madam, it is using expressions to one sense ^touch, for example) which are also metaphorical to another sense (say, sight) : as a result, a double light is shed on the subject for the hearer, the direct light of the natural use of the expression and the reflected light of the metaphor. It is evident that in these cases, Saunderson, with all his intelligence, was not aware of the full force of the terms he employed, since he only realised half of the ideas attached to these terms. But does not this happen to all of us at times? It may happen to idiots, who some- times make excellent jokes, and clever folk who say a foolish thing, without either being aware of it. I have observed the want of words produces the like effect in foreigners, who in an unfamiliar language are obliged to say everything in very few words, some of which they unknowingly use very happily. But every language being to writers of a lively imagination deficient in fit words, they are in the same case as clever foreigners : the situations invented by them, the delicate gradations they perceive in characters, the natural scenes they draw, are continually leading them away from ordinary locutions and causing them to adopt turns of phrases which never fail to charm when they are neither THE LETTER ON THE BLIND 101 precious nor obscure. These are faults which are more or less readily forgiven, according to the reader's wit and knowledge of the language. This is why M. de M * is the French author who most pleases the English, and Tacitus, of all the classics, bears the bell among the thinkers ; they do not attend to the licences of the style, it is only the truth of the expression which strikes them. Saunderson was extremely successful as professor of mathematics at the University of Cambridge. He gave lessons in optics, he lectured on the nature of light and colours, he explained the theory of vision ; he wrote on the properties of lenses, the phenomena of the rainbow, and many other subjects connected with sight and its organ. These facts lose much of their marvellous character when you consider that there are three distinct elements in a question in which both physics and geometry enter the phenomenon to be explained, the hypotheses of the geometrician, and the resultant calculation. Now it is manifest that, however great the penetration of the blind man, the phenomena of light and colour are unknown to him. The hypotheses he will understand, as all of them relate to palpable causes ; but the geometrician's reason for preferring them to others will be out of his ken, as in order to see that he must be able to compare the hypotheses 1 Naigeon, and after him the editor of 1818. have inserted, instead of the initials -I/, de J/ . . . in the original edition, M. de Montesquieu. This is a great mistake ; Diderot himself has given M. de Marivaux in the index of the 1749 and 1751 editions. The Esprit des Lois appeared in 1748, which might have caused this error on the part of the editors, who had not consulted the index. (Br) io- DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS themselves with the phenomena. Therefore the blind man takes -the hypotheses for what they are given him, a ray of light for a fine and elastic thread, or for a succession of minute bodies striking our eyes \vith incredible velocity, and he makes his calculations accordingly. The transition is made from physics to geometry, and the question becomes purely mathematical. But what are we to think of the results of the calculation ? Firstly, that it is sometimes extremely difficult to obtain them, and that it would be to little purpose that a man of science could form the most plausible hypotheses, were he not able to verify them by geometry ; accordingly the greatest physicists, Galileo, Descartes, and Newton, were great geometricians. Secondly, the results are more or less certain, as the preliminary hypotheses are more or less complex. When the calculation is based on a simple hypothesis, the conclusions have the validity of geometrical proofs. When there are a great many suppositions, the probability of each hypothesis being true diminishes in the ratio of the number of these hypotheses ; but on the other hand increases owing to the improbability that so many false hypotheses could be mutually corrective and produce a result confirmed by the phenomena. A parallel to this would be an addition, of which the sum was correct although the sum of groups of numbers had been wrongly added up. We must admit that such a result is possible, but at the same time you see that it would very seldom prove so. THE LETTER OX THE BLIXD 103 The greater the number of numbers to be added, the greater the probability of error in the addition of each, but at the same time this probability is lessened if the result of the operation be right. There are therefore a number of hypotheses, the certainty resulting from which would be the least possible. If I make A plus B plus C equal to 50, must I conclude from 50 being the real quantity of the phenomena that the suppositions represented by the letters A, B, C are true? Not at all, for there are numberless ways of subtracting from one of these letters and adding to the others which would always give 50 as the result. But the case of three combined hypotheses is perhaps one of the most dis favourable. One advantage of calculation which I must not omit is, that the contrariety found between the re- sult and the phenomenon excludes false hypotheses. If, a man of science proposes to find the curve formed by a ray of light in passing through the atmosphere, he must regulate himself by the density of the strata of air, the law of refraction, the nature and form of the luminous corpuscles, and perhaps other essential factors which he does not include in his calculation, either because he does not know them or because he deliberately leaves them out of consideration. He then determines the curvature of the ray. If the actual curve differs from that of his calculation, his hypotheses are incomplete or false. If the actual curvature agrees with that of his calculation, there are two alterna- 104 DIDEROT S PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS tives : first that his hypotheses were mutually cor- rective, secondly that they were correct. But which is true? He does not know, and yet that is the certitude to which he can attain. I read Saunderson's Elements of Algebra carefully in hopes of meeting what I was desirous of knowing from those who knew him intimately, and who have related some particulars of his life ; but my curiosity was baffled, and it occurred to me that elements of geometry from him would have been a work both more singular in itself and of greater use to us. We should have found in it definitions of point, line, surface, solid, angle, intersections of lines, and planes, in which I make no question but he would have proceeded on principles of very abstract meta- physics, closely allied to that of the idealists. Those philosophers, madam, are termed idealists who, conscious only of their own existence and of a succession of external sensations, do not admit any- thing else ; an extravagant system which should to my thinking have been the offspring of blindness itself ; and yet, to the disgrace of the human mind and philosophy, it is the most difficult to combat, though the most absurd. It is set forth with equal candour and lucidity by Doctor Berkeley, Bishop of Cloyne, in three dialogues. 1 It were to be wished that the author of the Essay on the Origin of Human Knowledge 2 would take this work into examination ; 1 frialogue s between Hylas and Philonoiis (1713), translated by the Abbe Gua de Malvin (1750). (A) a Condillac (1715-1780), whose Essay on the Origin of Human Knowledge had appeared anonymously in 1746. (A) THE LETTER OX THE BLIXD 105 he would there find matter for useful, agreeable, and ingenious observation for which, in a word, no person has a better talent. Idealism deserves an attack from his hand, and this hypothesis is a double incentive to him from its singularity, and much more from the difficulty of refuting it in accordance with his principles, which are the same as those of Berkeley. According to both, and according to reason, the terms essence, matter, substance, agent, etc., of themselves convey very little light to the mind. Moreover, as the author of the Essay on th? Origin of Human Knowledge judiciously observes, whether we go up to the heavens, or down to the deeps, we never get beyond ourselves, and it is only our own thoughts that we perceive. And this is the conclusion of Berkeley's first dialogue, and the foundation of his entire system. Would you not be curious to see a trial of strength between two enemies whose weapons are so much alike? If either got the better it would be he who wielded these weapons with the greater address ; the author of the Essay on the Origin of Human Knowledge has lately given in his Treatise on Systems additional proof of his adroitness and skill and shown himself a redoubtable foe to the systematics. We have wandered far from the blind, you will say. True, madam, but you must be so good as to allow me all these digressions ; I promised you a conversation, and I cannot keep my word without this indulgence. I have read as carefully as it was in my power io6 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS what Saunderson has said on the infinite ; and I assure you he had such very just and very clear notions on the subject that in his account most of our infinitarians would have been looked on but as blind. You yourself shall be judge : though this matter be somewhat difficult, and a little beyond your mathematical knowledge, I trust to bring it within your grasp and initiate you into the logic of the infinite. The case of this famous blind man proves that the sense of touch, when trained, can become more delicate than sight, for he distinguished genuine from counterfeit coins l by passing his hands over a number of these, although the counterfeits were sufficiently good imitations to deceive a clear- sighted connoisseur ; and he judged of the accuracy of a mathematical instrument by passing the tips of his fingers along its divisions. This is certainly more difficult than to judge by touch of the resem- blance of a bust to the person represented, and this shows that a blind people might have sculptors and put statues to the same use as among us to per- petuate the memory of great deeds, and of persons dear to them ; and in my opinion feeling such statues would give them a keener pleasure than we have in seeing them. What a delight to a passion- ate lover to draw his hand over beauties which he would know again, when illusion, which would act more potently on the blind than on those who see, 1 Memoirs of the life and character of Dr Nicholas Saunderson m Saunderson's Mfetra, vol. i, p. xi (1740), THE LETTER ON THE BLIND 107 should come to reanimate them ! But perhaps, as he would take a deeper pleasure in the memory, his grief would be the keener for the loss of the original. Saunderson, like the blind man of Puisaux, was affected by the smallest atmospheric change, and could recognise, especially in still weather, the presence of objects not far from him. It is related of him that being present during some astronomical observations taken in a garden, the clouds which hid the face of the sun every now and then from the spectators at the same time caused such a change in the action of the rays on his face as signified to him the moments which favoured or impeded the experiments. You may, perhaps, think that some change in the eye might indicate to him the presence of light, but not of distant objects, and I would have supposed so myself, but for the fact that Saunderson had lost not only his sight but its organ. Saunderson, then, saw by means of his skin, *and this integument of his was so keenly sensitive that with a little practice he could certainly have re- cognised the features of a friend traced upon his hand, and would have exclaimed, as the result of successive sensations caused by the pencil: "That is so-and-so." Thus the blind have likewise a paint- ing, in which their own skin serves as the canvas. These are no wild fancies, and I am sure if the little mouth of M were traced on your hand, you would immediately recognise it. Yet you must allow the blind man would find this an easier task than you, io8 DIDEROrS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS accustomed though you are to see and admire that mouth. For two or three elements enter into your recognition : the comparison of the tracery on your hand with the picture formed on the ground of your eye ; the recollection of the manner in which we are affected by things felt, and of the manner with which we are affected by things we have only seen and admired ; finally, the application of these data to the question of the draughtsman, who asks you when he draws with his pencil a mouth on the skin of your hand : " Whose mouth is this which I am drawing ? " Whereas the sum of the sensations aroused by a mouth laid on the blind man's hand is the same as the sum of the successive sensations caused by the draughtsman's pencil. I might add to this account of Saunderson and the blind man of Puisaux, Didymus of Alexandria, Eusebius the Asiatic, and Nicaise of Mechlin, 1 and some other people who, though lacking one sense, seemed so far above the level of the rest of mankind that the poets might without exaggeration have feigned the jealous gods to have deprived them of it, from fear lest mortals should equal them. For what was Tiresias, who had penetrated the secrets of the gods, but a blind philosopher whose memory has been handed down to us by fable? But let us return to Saunderson and follow the history of this extraordinary man to his grave. When he was at the point of death, 2 a clergyman of great ability, Mr Gervase Holmes, was summoned 1 See note 2, pp. 219, 220. - See Introduction, pp. 10-15, l8 > *9 THE LETTER ON THE BLIXD 109 to his side, and they held a discussion upon the existence of God, some fragments of which are extant, and which I will translate to the best of my ability, for they are well worth it. The clergyman began by haranguing on the wonders of nature. "Ah, sir," replied the blind philosopher, " don't talk to me of this magnificent spectacle, which it has never been my lot to enjoy. 1 have been condemned to spend my life in darkness, and you cite wonders quite out of my understanding, and which are only evidence for you and for those who see as you do. If you want to make me believe in God you must make me touch Him." "Sir/' returned the clergy- man, very appositely, "touch yourself, and you wilj recognise the Deity in the admirable mechanism of your organs." "Mr Holmes," replied Saunderson, "I must repeat it, all that does not appear so admirable to me as to you. But even if the animal mechanism were as perfect as you maintain, and I dare say it is (for you are a worthy man and would scorn to impose on me), what relation is there between such mechanism and a supremely intelligent Being ? If it fills you with astonishment, that is perhaps because you are accustomed to treat as miraculous everything which strikes you as beyond your own powers. I have been myself so often an object of admiration to you, that I have not a very high idea of your idea of the miraculous. I have had visits from people from all parts of England who could not conceive how I could work at geometry : i io fl/DEROrS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS you must allow such folk not to have been very exact in their notions of the possibility of things. \Ye think a certain phenomenon beyond human power and we cry out at once : c 'Tis the handiwork of a god J ; our vanity will stick at nothing less. Why can we not season our talk with a little less pride and a little more philosophy ? If nature offers us a knotty problem, let us leave it for what it is, without calling in to cut it the hand of a being who immediately becomes a fresh knot and harder to untie than the first. Ask an Indian how the earth hangs suspended in mid-air, and he will tell you that it is carried on the back of an elephant ; and what carries the elephant? A tortoise. And the tortoise? You pity the Indian, and one might say to yourself as to him : * My good friend Mr Holmes, confess your ignorance, and drop the elephant and the tortoise,'" 1 Saunderson paused, apparently waiting for a reply, but what possible reply was there to the blind man ? Mr Holmes availed himself of his good opinion of his probity and of the abilities of Newton, Leibniz, Clarke, and some of his fellow-countrymen, men of the highest genius, who had all been im- pressed by the wonders of nature and recognised an intelligent being as its creator. This was certainly the clergyman's strongest argument. The blind man admitted that it would be presumptuous to deny what such a man as Newton had acquiesced in ; yet he represented to the clergyman that Newton's 1 See note 3, pp. 221, 222. . THE LETTER ON THE BLIXD in evidence was not of that weight to him, as that of all nature to Newton ; while Xewton believed on God's word, he was reduced to believe on Newton's word. " Consider, Mr Holmes," he added, "what a confidence I must have in your word and in Newton's. Though I see nothing, I admit there is in everything an admirable design and order. I hope you will not demand more. I take your word for the present state of the universe, and in return keep the liberty of thinking as I please on its ancient and primitive state, with relation tu which you are as blind as myself. Here you will have no witnesses to confront me with, and your eyes are quite use- less. Think, if you choose, that the design which strikes you so powerfully has always subsisted, but allow me my own contrary opinion, and allow me to believe that if we went back to the origin oi things and scenes and perceived matter in motion and the evolution from chaos, we should meet with a number of shapeless creatures, instead of a few creatures highly organised. I make no criticism on the present state of things, but I can ask you some questions as to the past. For instance, I may ask you and Leibniz and Clarke and Newton, who told you that in the first instances of the formation of animals some were not headless and others footless ? I might affirm that such an one had no stomach, another no intestines, that some which seemed to deserve a long duration from their possession of a stomach, palate, and teeth came to an end owing ii2 DIDEROPS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS to some defect in the heart or lungs ; that monsters mutually destroyed one another ; that all the defective combinations of matter disappeared, and that those only survived whose mechanism was not defective in any important particular and who were able to support and perpetuate themselves. 1 4< Suppose the first man had his larynx closed, or had lacked suitable food, or had been defective in the organs of generation, or had failed to find a mate, or had propagated in another species, what then, Mr Holmes, would have been the fate 01 the human race ? It would have been still merged in the general depuration of the universe, and that proud being who calls himself man, dissolved and dispersed among the molecules of matter, would have remained perhaps for ever hidden among the number of mere possibilities. If shapeless creatures had never existed, you would not fail to assert that none will ever appear, and that I am throwing myself headlong into chimerical fancies, but the order is not even now so perfect as to exclude the occasional appearance of monstrosities." Then, turning towards the clergyman, he added, " Look at me, Mr Holmes. I have no eyes. What have we done, you and I, to God, that one of us has this organ while the other has not?" Saunderson uttered these words in such a sincere and heartfelt tone that the clergyman and the rest of the company could not remain insensible to his 1 This is the thesis of Lucretius, and the theory of the survival of the hltest.(A) THE LETTER ON THE BLIND 113 suffering, and began to weep bitterly. He noticed it and said to the clergyman, "Mr Holmes, I was aware of the kindness of your heart, and I am very grateful for the expression of it you have given me just now ; but if you love me, do not grudge me my dying consolation of never having caused anyone affliction." Then, continuing the conversation in a firmer tone, he added: "I conjecture, then, that in the beginning, when matter in a state of ferment brought this world into being, creatures like myself were of very common occurrence. But might not worlds too be in the same case ? How many faulty and incomplete worlds have been dispersed and perhaps form again, and are dispersed at every instant in remote regions of space which I cannot touch nor you behold, but where motion continues and will continue to combine masses of matter, until they have found some arrangement in which they may finally persevere ? O philosophers, travel with me to the confines of this universe, beyond the point where I feel and you behold organised beings ; cast your eyes over this new ocean, and search in its aimless and lawless agitations for vestiges of that Intelligent Being whose wisdom fills you with such wonder and admiration here ! "But what is the use of taking you out of your element? What is this world, Mr Holmes, but a complex, subject to cycles of change, all of which show a continual tendency to destruction ; a rapid succession of beings that appear one by one, flourish 8 H4 DJDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS and disappear ; a merely transitory symmetry and momentary appearance of order? A moment ago I reproached you for estimating the perfection of things by your own capacity ; I might accuse you here of measuring duration by your own existence. You judge of the phases of the world's existence as the ephemeral insect of yours. The world seems to you eternal, just as you seem eternal to the creatures of a day ; and the insect is more reasonable than you. What a prodigious series of ephemeral genera- tions witness to your eternity, what an immense tradition ! Yet we shall all pass away without a possibility of denoting the real extent which we took up, or the precise time of our duration. Time, matter, and space are perhaps but a point, " During this conversation Saunderson became more excited than his state of health would permit, and an attack of delirium ensued, which lasted several hours. At its close he cried, " O thou God of Clarke and Newton, have mercy on me!" and expired. Such was the end of Saunderson. You see, madam, that all the arguments of the clergyman he took exception to were not of a character to con- vince a blind man. What a disgrace to men who have no better argument than he ; men who have eyes, to whom the marvellous spectacle of nature from sunrise to the setting of the smallest stars reveals the existence and glory of its Maker ! They have sight, which Saunderson was deprived of, but Saunderson was blessed with a purity of life and 'THE LETTER ON THE BLIND 115 uprightness which \ve look for In vain in them. Accordingly they lead the life of the blind, and Saunderson died as if he knew the light. The voice of nature made itself clear to him by the media of the senses he possessed, and his evidence is the more convincing against those who obstinately shut their eyes and ears. Was not the true God more completely veiled by the mists of paganism for a Socrates, than for the blind Saunderson, who never enjoyed the spectacle of nature ? I am very sorry, madam, both for your sake and mine, that no further interesting particulars of this famous blind man have been handed down. His conversation would perhaps have afforded more light than all our experiments. Tho^e about him must have been devoid of the philosophic spirit. I make an exception in favour of his pupil, Mr William Inchlif, who only saw Saunderson during his last moments, and who took down his last words, which I should advise all who know English to read in the original, printed in Dublin in 1747, and entitled The Life and Character of Dr Nicholas Saunderson^ late Lucasian Professor of the Mathematicks in the University of Cambridge ; by his disciple and friend William Inchlif, hsq.^ They w T ill find a charm, and a vigour in this, scarce ever paralleled, but which I do not flatter myself I have conveyed in translation, in spite of all my care. 1 By rendering a Dr Inchlif responsible for his imaginary reconstruc- tion of Saunderson 's last moments Diderot alienated the sympathies of England. (A) 1 16 D1DEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS He married in 1713 the daughter of Mr Dickons, rector of Boxworth, in the county of Cambridge, and had by her a son and daughter who are still living. His farewell to his family was exceedingly moving. " I go," said he, "to our common destination; spare me laments which unman and unnerve. The expressions of grief which escape you only make me conscious of my own. I gladly give up a life which has been for me a long desire, a constant privation. Live on, as virtuous as I, but more fortunate, and learn to die with equal calm." He then took his wife's hand, which he held for a moment clasped in his own ; he turned his face towards her as if he desired to see her ; he blessed his children, embraced them, and begged them to leave him, because they caused him greater grief than the approach of death. England is the land of philosophy and of scientific inquiry, yet without Mr Inchlif we should only know what the common man could have narrated of Saunderson ; for instance, that he recognised places he had once visited by the sound the walls and pavement reflected, and many similar anecdotes, all equally common to the majority of the blind. Strange ! Are blind men of such high intellectual abilities as Saunderson of common occurrence in England, and are men born blind who lecture on optics to be met with every day? People try to give those born blind the gift of sight, but, rightly considered, science would be equally advanced by questioning a sensible blind THE LETTER ON THE BLIND 117 man. We should learn to understand his psychology and should compare it with ours, and perhaps we should thereby come to a solution of the difficulties which make the theory of vision and of the senses so intricate and so confused. But I own I cannot conceive what information we could expect from a man who had just undergone a painful operation upon a very delicate organ which is deranged by the smallest accident and which when sound is a very untrustworthy guide to those who have for a long time enjoyed its use. For my part, as to the theory of the senses, 1 would sooner hear a metaphysician who was acquainted with the principles of meta- physics, the elements of mathematics, and the con- formation of the organs of sense, than an uneducated man whose sight was first due to an operation for cataract. I would have less confidence in the im- pressions of a person seeing for the first time than in the discoveries of a philosopher who had profoundly meditated on the subject in the dark ; or, to adopt the language of the poets, who had put out his eyes in order to be the better acquainted with vision. To obtain some certainty in such experiments the subject must at least have been prepared a long time beforehand ; he should be made a philosopher no rapid process even with a philosopher for teacher ! And imagine the task if the teacher were not enlightened, or (worse still) fondly and mistakenly imagined himself enlightened ! It would be better to postpone the investigation to a considerable period after the operation. To do this, the patient would i IS DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS have to remain in darkness, and the investigator would have to see to it that his wound was healed and his eyes perfectly sound. I would not expose him to full daylight for the first time. A strong light dazzles our eyes ; what effect will it not have on an organ which cannot but be extremely tender and sensitive, and which has never yet felt any impression to blunt it? But this is only the beginning. It would be a difficult and delicate task to reap any benefit even from a person thus prepared, and to adapt our questions so that he may precisely say only what passes in himself. This interrogatory should be held in presence of the Academy ; or rather, to avoid the presence of idle spectators, only such as deserve that distinction by their knowledge of philosophy, anatomy, etc., should be invited. The task would not be beneath the intelligence of the best and wisest of men ; to train and question one born blind would be an occupation worthy of the combined talents of Newton, Descartes, Locke and Leibniz. I will end my letter, which I own is already too lengthy, by a problem which was propounded some time ago. Some reflections upon Saunderson's singular condition tend to show that it has never been absolutely solved. Suppose one blind from birth has been taught to distinguish by touch a cube and a sphere of the same metal and of approximately the same size, so that when he touches them he can say which is the cube and which is the sphere. THE LETTER ON THE BLIND 1 19 Suppose the cube and sphere placed on a table and the blind man suddenly to see ; can he dis- tinguish the cube from the sphere by sight without touch ? Mr Molyneux first stated this problem and attempted to solve it. He declared that the blind man would not distinguish between the cube and the sphere; "for, "said he, "though he has learnt by experience the effect of a sphere and a cube upon the sense of touch, he does not yet know that what affects his sense of touch in such and such a manner must affect his sight thus or thus ; nor that the pro- jecting angle of the cube which presses against his hand should appear to his eyes as it actually does appear in the cube." Locke, 1 when consulted on this point, said: "I certainly agree with Mr Molyneux's opinion. I believe the blind man incapable at first sight of affirming with any certainty which was the cube and which the sphere if he merely looked at them, although, if he touched them, he could name them and distinguish between them by the difference of their shape, which he would recognise by touch. " The Abb de Condillac, 2 whose Essay on the Origin of Human Knowledge you have read with so much pleasure and profit, and whose excellent Treatise on Systems accompanies this letter, makes an original contribution to the question. I shall not repeat his arguments here, since you will have the pleasure of reading his book in which they are expounded in i See note 4, pp. ^2, 223, 8 See note 5, pp. 223-5, 120 DIDEROrS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS such an entertaining and yet such a philosophical manner that it would be a mistake on my part to tear them from their context. I shall merely observe that they all tend to prove that the born-blind either sees nothing, or distinguishes between the sphere and the cube ; and that the conditions that these two bodies should be of the same metal and of approximately the same size (which was postulated in the problem) are unnecessary, which cannot be disputed ; for he might have said, if there be no essential connection between the sensations of the sight and the touch ('as Messrs Locke and Molyneux assert), they must admit that a body may to the eye appear to have two feet in diameter which yet would vanish on being touched. De Condillac adds, how- ever, that if the blind man sees bodies and dis- tinguishes their forms, and yet hesitates what to think about them, it must be from metaphysical reasons, and those not a little subtle, which I shall presently explain. We have here two different opinions on the same question a difference between philosophers of the 1 highest rank. One would suppose, after the problem had been studied by men such as Messrs Molyneux, Locke and the Abb de Condillac, that nothing more could be said ; but the same thing can be viewed from so many different sides that it is not strange if they have not exhausted all its possibilities. Those who declare that a man blind from birth could not distinguish between a cube and a sphere have set out by assuming a fact which perhaps should THE LETTER ON THE BLIND 121 have been investigated ; that is, whether a blind man who has had his cataracts removed is in a condition to use his eyes immediately after the operation. They merely say: "The blind man, comparing the ideas of spheres and cubes which he has received by the sense of touch with those received by sight, will necessarily know them to be the same ; and it would be indeed odd if he were to name that body a cube which gives the eye the idea of a sphere, and sphere that which gives the idea of a cube. He will there- fore call those bodies spheres and cubes at sight which he called spheres and cubes by the sense of touch." But how do their antagonists reply ? They have also taken for granted that the blind man could see immediately his organ was perfect ; they supposed that an eye couched for cataract was like an arm that ceases to be paralysed. As the latter does not need exercise before it feels, they said, neither does the former before it sees; and they added: "Let us grant the blind man a little more philosophy than you afford him, and after carrying on the reason- ing where you left it, he will continue thus : * But still, who is to assure me that when I approach these bodies and touch them with my hands they will not on a sudden deceive my expectation, and that a cube will not give me the sensation of a sphere and a sphere of a cube ? Experience alone can teach me whether there be an analogy between sight and touch. The reports of these two senses may well be contradictory without my knowing it ; nay, I 122 DTDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS should perhaps suppose what is actually present to the sight to be only a mere appearance, had I not been informed that they are the very same bodies I had touched. This object certainly seems to be the body which I called a cube ; and that, the body I called a sphere ; but the question is, not what 1 think, but what is ; and I am not in a position to answer the latter question satisfactorily.' " The line of argument, says the author of the Essay on the Origin of Human Knowledge, would be extremely perplexing to him who had been born blind, and I see nothing but experience which can furnish an answer to it. It seems probable that the Abbe de Condillac means only the experiment repeated by the blind man himself on a second handling of these bodies. You will soon perceive why I make this point That able metaphysician might have added that the blind man would be the more inclined to suppose that two senses might be mutually contradictory, as he conceives that a mirror makes them mutually contradictory, as I have noticed already. De Condillac proceeds to observe that Molyneux has confused the issues of the problem by laying down several conditions which are irrelevant to the metaphysical difficulties which the blind man would experience. This criticism is the more just, as the supposition of the blind man being acquainted with metaphysics is not at all out of the way ; because the experiment in all such philosophical questions should be accounted to be made on a philosopher that Is THE LETTER ON THE BLIND 123 to say, on a person who perceives In the questions propounded all that his reason and the state of his organs permit him to perceive. Such, briefly, are, madam, the pros and cons of the problem ; and you shall now see by my examination of It how very far they, who asserted that the blind man would see geometrical figures and distinguish between them, were from realising that they were right ; and what good reason their opponents had to think that they were not in the wrong. This problem of the blind man, stated in some- what more general terms than by Molyneux, embraces two problems which we will consider separately. \Ve may ask (i ) if the blind man would see immediately after the operation for cataract ; (2) supposing he is able to see, could he see well enough to distinguish between figures ; could he, in seeing them, correctly give them the same names which he gave them by the sense of touch ; and if he can, prove that these names are the right ones ? Will the man born blind see immediately after the cure of the organ ? Those who maintain that he will not see, say: " Directly the blind man is able to use his eyes, all the scene before him is represented at the back of the eye. This image, which is composed of a number of objects concen- trated in a very small space, is but a confused mass of figures which he will not be able to distinguish. People are on the whole agreed that it is only ex- perience which can enable him to judge of the dis- tance of objects, and that he is obliged to approach, i2 4 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS touch, draw back from, and again approach and touch them to assure himself that they are not part of himself and are foreign to his essence ; that he is now near and now far from them. Why should not experience be a necessary preliminary for per- ceiving them ? Without previous experience he who perceives objects for the first time would suppose, when he is out of sight of them, that they had ceased to exist ; for it is only our experience of per- manent objects and such as we find again in the same place where we left them which evidences the continuity of their existence when out of our sight. It is perhaps for this reason that children are so readily consoled for toys taken from them. It cannot be said that they promptly forget them, for some children only two and a half years old know a considerable number of words of a language and are more at a loss to pronounce them than to retain them. Now, this is a proof of childhood's being the very season of memory. Is it not a more likely hypothesis that children think that what they no longer see no longer exists, especially as their joy when things they have lost sight of appear again is mixed with surprise ? Nurses help them to acquire the notion of the continuance of absent persons by playing a game which consists in hiding the face, and showing it again. Thus they learn a hundred times in a quarter of an hour that what ceases to appear does not necessarily cease to exist. Whence it follows that we owe the notion of the continuous existence THE LETTER ON THE BLIND 125 of objects to experience, of their distance to the sense of touch ; that the eye may perhaps have to learn to see as the tongue to speak ; that it would not be surprising should the aid of one of the senses be necessary to another ; and that touch, which ascertains the existence of objects exterior to ourselves when present to our eyes, is likewise the sense to which the confirmation not only of their figures, and other details of these objects, but even their presence, is reserved. To these arguments may be added the famous experiment of Cheselden. 1 The young man from whose eyes this skilful surgeon removed cataracts was for a long time unable to distinguish dimensions, distances, positions, or even figures. An object an inch in size held before his eye so as to hide a house from him appeared as large as the house itself. All he saw seemed as close to his eye as the object he touched to the skin. He could not distinguish what he judged round by touch from what he had judged angular ; nor distinguish by sight whether what he had felt to be above or beneath him were in reality above or beneath him. He eventually succeeded, but not without difficulty, in perceiving that his house was larger than his room, but he could not conceive how this could be ascertained by sight. Repeated experiments were necessary before he became assured of paintings representing solid bodies ;' and when he was quite convinced by looking at pictures that what he saw was not bare surfaces, 1 See note 6, p. 225. 126 DfDEROrS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS on putting his hand to a picture he was vastly surprised at finding a plane surface without any relief. Me then asked which was deceptive, the sense of touch or the sense of sight ? Painting likewise has the same effect on savages. They take the painted figures for living men, question them and are astonished at receiving no answer ; and this error in them certainly did not proceed from their not being accustomed to see. But what can be answered to the other difficulties ? That the trained and practised eye of a man sees better than the weak and untrained organ of an infant, or of one born blind who has had his eyes couched. Look, madam, at the proofs adduced by the Abbe de Condillac at the end of his Essay on the Origin of Human Knowledge^ where he also adduces Cheselden's experiments as related by Voltaire. The effects of light upon an eye for the first time so affected, and the conditions required in humours of that organ, the cornea, the crystalline lens, etc., are clearly and ably specified therein, and leave little doubt that the vision of an infant opening its eyes for the first time, or a blind person who has just been operated upon, is very imperfect We must, therefore, admit we perceive a multitude of details in objects unperceived by the infant or one born blind, though these objects are equally represented at the back of their eyes ; for objects to strike us is not enough we must further attend to these experiences ; that, consequently, we see nothing the first time we use our eyes ; and during THE LETTER ON THE BLIND 12; the first moments of sight we only receive a mass of confused sensations, which are only disentangled after a time and by a process of reflection. It is by experience alone that we learn to compare our sensations with what occasions them ; that sensa- tions having no essential resemblance with their objects, it is from experience that we are to inform ourselves concerning analogies which seem to be merely positive. In short, that touch is of great service in giving the eye an accurate knowledge of the conformity of the object to the sense-impression received of it is unquestionable ; and I am much Inclined to think that were not everything in nature subject to laws infinitely general if, for instance, the pricking of certain hard bodies were painful, and that of certain other bodies pleasurable we should die before we had received the hundred- millionth fraction of the experiences necessary for the preservation of our body and our well-being. I am not, however, of opinion that the eye is incapable of learning, or, if I may say so, of ex- perimenting alone. To ascertain the existence and form of objects by touch, there is no necessity of seeing ; why should touch be necessary for complete realisation of the same objects by sight ? I am awake to all the advantages of touch ; I have not disguised them in these observations on Saunderson or the blind man of Puisaux ; but I cannot allow it that prerogative. It is easy to see that the use of one sense may be perfected and accelerated by the observations of another ; but not that there is an US DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS essential interdependence between their functions. There exist certainly properties in bodies which we should never perceive without touch ; and by touch we learn the presence of certain details invisible to the eye, which only becomes aware of these when informed by the sense of touch ; but their services are mutual ; and in the case of persons who have sight more highly developed than touch it is the former which warns the latter of the existence 01 objects and of details which would pass unnoticed from their minuteness. If unknown to you a piece of paper or some smooth, thin, and flexible substance were placed between your thumb and index finger, it is your eye alone which would inform you that the contact between your two fingers was not direct. It would be much more difficult, I may cursorily add, to deceive a blind man than a person used to see in this. An eye which is in sound condition and freely exercised might have some difficulty in convincing itself that exterior objects are not part of itself; that some things are distant, some near ; that they have forms ; that some are larger than others ; that they have depth, etc. ; still, I make no doubt that at length it would come to see them, and to see them so distinctly as to distinguish at least their more obvious limits. To deny this would be to set aside the aim and object of the organs; it would be forgetting the chief phenomena of vision ; it would be concealing from oneself that there is no painter of such skill THE LETTER ON THE BLIND 129 as to rival the beauty and exactness of the miniatures which are painted in the back of your eyes ; that there is nothing more exact than the likeness of the representation to the object itself; that. the canvas of this picture is not so very small, that there is no confusion among the various forms, and that they occupy about a square half-inch ; and that nothing is more difficult to explain than how the sense of touch would begin to teach the eye to see were the use of the latter organ absolutely impossible without the aid of the former. But, instead of bare presumptions, I ask you whether it is touch that teaches the eye to distinguish colours? I do not suppose such an extraordinary claim will be made for touch ; and this being so, it follows that if a blind man who has just been given the gift of sight is shown a black cube or a red sphere on a white background, he will immediately discern the several outlines of these figures. Delay will be caused, some may object, by the time which must elapse for the humours of the eye to assume their proper dispositions, for the cornea to assume the convexity requisite for vision, for the pupil to be susceptible of the dilation and contraction proper to it, for the filaments of the retina to be sensitive in the right degree to the action of light, for the crystalline to exercise its forward and back- ward movement or for the muscles to fulfil their functions well, for the optic nerves to become accustomed to the transmission of sensation, for the entire eyeball to accommodate itself to all the 9 130 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS necessary dispositions, and for all its component parts to combine in the execution of that miniature, which so much illustrates the demonstration that the eye will bring itself to the requisite experience. I own that, plain as the picture is which I have now represented to the eye of one born blind, he will not be able clearly to distinguish its parts until all these above conditions are combined ; but that is perhaps the work of a moment ; and it would not be difficult, by applying the aforesaid argument to a complicated mechanism such as a watch, to prove by enumerating all the movements which take place in the drum, the fusee, the wheels, the pallets, the pendulum, etc., that the hand would take a fortnight in moving the space of a second. If it is objected that these movements are simulta- neous, I reply that so perhaps are the movements in the eye when it opens for the first time, and most of the consecutive judgments. Whatever are the conditions in the eye requisite for vision, it must be granted that it is not touch which imparts them to it, that the organ acquires them independ- ently ; consequently, will succeed in distinguishing the figures represented therein without the aid of another sense. But when does this occur?, some will say. Perhaps far sooner than is thought. When we went together to the Jardin Royal, do you remember the experiment with the concave mirror and your fright when you saw the point of a sword making at you with the same swiftness as the point THE LETTER ON THE BLIXD 131 of that which you pushed towards the surface of the mirror ? And yet you were sufficiently accustomed to refer objects represented in mirrors to something beyond them. Experience, therefore, is not so very necessary, nor so infallible as imagined, for perceiving objects or their images where they are. Your very parrot gives proof of it. The first time he saw himself in a mirror, he touched it with his beak, and as he did not reach himself (whom he took for a fellow-parrot) he walked round the mirror. I am not for laying more than due weight on the instance of the parrot ; still, it is an experiment with an animal in which preconceived notions cannot be supposed to have any share. Yet if I were told that a man born blind saw nothing for the space of two months, I should not be surprised. I shall only conclude from it the necessity of the organs becoming practised, not the necessity of touch. It will be another reason why it is important to let such a person remain for some time in the dark, when he is to be the subject of experiment ; to allo\v him the opportunity of exer- cising his eye, which will be done more conveniently in the dark than in full daylight ; and only to permit a kind of twilight during the experiments, or at least to arrange for the increasing or diminish- ing of light at pleasure in the spot where the experiments take place. I shall only be the more inclined to agree that such experiments will always be very difficult and uncertain ; and that the best and shortest (though superficially the longest) way 132 DIDEROT'S PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS would be to arm the subject with a philosophical training sufficient to enable him to compare the two conditions he has known, and to acquaint us with the difference between the state of a blind person and of one who has his sight. Once more, what precision is to be expected from one who has not the habit of thought and analysis, and who, like Cheselden's blind man, is so ignorant of the benefits of sight as to be insensible to his misfortune, not conceiving that the lack of this sense very much impairs his pleasure? Saunderson, who certainly deserves the name of philosopher, was not thus indifferent, and I doubt much whether he would have agreed with the author of the excellent Treatise on Systems ; I suspect the latter to have fallen into a ** system" himself when he writes that, "had the life of man been only an uninterrupted sensation of pleasure or of pain, happy without prospect of pain, wretched without any prospect of pleasure, he would have rejoiced or suffered ; and that if he were so constituted, he would not have looked about him to discover if some influence were well disposed towards him, or desired to injure him ; it is only the alterna- tion between these two conditions which causes him to reflect," etc. Can you believe, madam, that by a clear train of reasoning (for that is the Author's method of philosophising) he would ever have been led to this conclusion? It is not with happiness and misery as with light and darkness ; the one is not simply the privation of the other. We might, THE LETTER OX THE BLIXD 133 perhaps, have entertained the idea that happiness was as essential to us as existence and thought, had we enjoyed it without intermission ; but I canrot say the same with regard to unhappines?. It would have been very natural to look on it as a forced condition, to feel oneself innocent, yet to believe oneself guilty and to accuse or excuse nature as at present. Does the Abbe de Condillac suppose that a child in pain only cries from his pain not having been without intermission from his birth? If he replies that st existence and pain would be one and indivis- ible for one who had always suffered, and that such an one could not imagine cessation of suffering with- out cessation of his existence," I make reply : ** The man living in continual misery possibly might not have said, 4 What have I done that I should suffer thus?' but why might he not have said, * What have 1 done that I should be brought into being ? ' " At the same time, I see no reason why he should not have used his two synonymous verbs, I exist and I suffer, the one in prose, the other in poetry, as we use the two expressions, I live and I breathe. Moreover, madam, you will observe better than I do that this passage of the Abbe de Condillac's is admirably fine, and I fear you may say, after com- paring my criticism with his reflections, you prefer an error of Montaigne's to a truth of Charron's. You may blame my continual digressions. But digressions are of the essence of this treatise. Now my opinion on the two foregoing questions is this : the first time the eyes of one born blind open to the 134 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS light, he will see nothing at all ; some time will be necessary for his eye to practise sight ; it will practise alone and without the aid of touch, and will eventually distinguish not only colours but the main outlines of objects. Supposing he acquired this aptitude in a very short space of time, or acquired it b} T using his eyes in the dark apartment in which he had been confined and urged to use that exercise for some time after the operation and before the experiments ; let us now see whether he would recognise at sight the bodies he had touched, so as to give them the proper appellations. This is the final question. In order to treat "the question in the manner you will appreciate for you like method I will classify the persons on whom the. experiment might be made. If they are dullards without education and knowledge and also unprepared, I hold that when the operation for cataract has completely removed the defect of the eye and the eye is in a healthy state, objects would be very distinctly pictured in it ; but such patients, being unaccustomed to any kind of reasoning and not knowing anything of sensation or idea, would be unable to compare the sensations they had received by touch with those they now receive by sight, and would at once exclaim, "There is a round, there is a square," so that their judgment is not to be relied on ; or even they will possibly own that they saw nothing in the objects jpresent to their sight like what they have handled. THE LETTER ON THE BLIXD 135 Another class there is, who by comparing the forms they see with the bodies that had previously made an impression upon their hands, and mentally applying touch to distant objects, would describe one body as a square, and another as a circle with- out well knowing why, their comparison of the ideas they have acquired by sight not being sufficiently distinct in their minds to convince their judgment. I pass to a third class of subject, a metaphysician. He, I make no doubt, would, directly he began to see objects clearly, reason as if he had seen these bodies all his life ; and after comparing the ideas acquired by sight with those acquired by touch he would declare as confidently as you or I : " I am very much inclined to think that this is the body which I have always called a circle, and that again what I named a square, but will not assert it to be really so. What is to prevent their disappearance if I were to touch them? How am I to know whether the bodies I see are also meant to be touched? I do not know whether visible things are palpable ; but were I assured of this, and did I take the word of those about me that what I see is really what I have touched, I should be no better off! These bodies may transform themselves in my hands and transmit on contact sensations quite different from those resulting from sight. ** Gentlemen," would he conclude, "this body appears to be the square, that the circle ; but that they are the same to touch as to sight is what I have no know- ledge of/* 136 DIDEROT S PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS If \ve take as our subject a geometrician instead of a metaphysician, he will likewise say of the two figures he has before his eyes, one is what he used to call a square, the other what he used to call a circle : " For I see," he would add, " that it is only in the former I could arrange my threads and insert my large-headed pins which denoted the angles of the square ; and only in the latter figure I could place the threads I required to demonstrate the properties of a circle. Here is a circle, then, and here is a square. But," he would have added with Locke, * ' perhaps when I lay my hands on these figures they will change one into another, so that the same figure would serve me in demonstrating the properties of a circle to the blind and the pro- perties of a square to the sighted. I might possibly see a square and at the same time feel a circle. No, " he would have continued, " I am wrong. Those to whom I demonstrated the properties of the circle and the square had not their hands on my abacus, and did not touch the threads which I had stretched to outline my figures, and yet they understood me ; they therefore did not see a square when I felt a circle, otherwise we should have been at cross- purposes ; I should have been outlining one figure and demonstrating the properties of another, I should have given them a straight line for the arc of a circle, and an arc for a straight line : but as they all understood me, all men see alike : what they saw as a square, I see as a square ; what they saw as a circle, 1 see as a circle. So this is what I have THE LETTER ON THE BLIND 137 always called a square and that is what I have always called a circle." I have substituted a circle for a sphere and a square for a cube, because there Is reason to think that we only judge of distances by experience ; and of course he who uses his eyes for the first time sees only surfaces without knowing anything of projection, since a projection consists in certain points appearing nearer to us than others. But even if the blind man were able in his first attempt to judge of the projection of solidity of bodies and distinguish not only a circle from a square but likewise a sphere from a cube, yet I do not therefore think that this will hold good with regard to the case of more composite bodies. There is reason to suppose that Monsieur de Reaumur's blind woman distinguished between colours, but the odds are thirty to one that what she said of the sphere and the cube was purely guesswork. I am firmly persuaded that it was not possible for her (without inspiration) to recognise her gloves, her dressing-gown, and her shoes. These objects are so composite and full of detail ; there is so little resemblance between their total shape and that of the limbs they are designed to adorn or cover that Saunderson would have been infinitely more perplexed to find out the use of his mortar-board than d'Alembert or Clairaut to dis- cover the use of his tables. Saunderson would infallibly have supposed a geometrical relation between the object and its use, hence he would have recognised that his skull-cap was made for his head, for this had no arbitrary 138 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS form to confuse him. But what would he have thought of the points and tassel of his mortar- board ? What was the use of the tassel, or why four points rather than six? And, these two ornamental peculiarities would for him have been the source of a number of absurd theories, or rather an excellent satire upon what we call good taste. Taking everything into mature consideration, it will be admitted that the difference between a person who has always seen, but to whom the use of an object is unknown, and one who knows the use of an object, but has never seen, is not to the latter's advantage. Yet, do you think, madam, if you were shown a head-dress to-day for the first time, you would ever guess it to be an ornament, and particularly intended for the head ? But if it be more difficult for one born blind and seeing for the- first time to form a correct idea of complex objects, what is there to prevent him taking a person dressed and sitting motionless in an arm- chair for a machine or a piece of furniture, and a tree with its leaves and branches tossed by the wind for a self-moving, animated, and thinking being ? How much our senses suggest to us ; and were it not for our eyes how apt should we be to suppose that a block of marble thinks and feels ! It is certain, therefore, that Saunderson would have been assured of his not being mistaken in the judgment he had just given of the circle and the square, and that there are cases when the reasoning and experience of others are of value in elucidating THE LETTER ON THE BLIND 139 the relation of sight to touch, and in teaching that what a thing is to the eye, it is likewise to touch. It would, however, be not the less essential in demonstrating some proposition of universal applica- tion (as it is termed) to test the proof by depriving it of the evidence of the senses ; for you are very well aware, madam, that if some person attempted to prove to you that two parallel lines seen in perspective are to be represented in a picture by two converging lines, because the two sides of an avenue appear to converge, it would be forgetting that the proposition is as true for one that is blind as for himself. But the foregoing supposition of one born blind suggests two others : firstly, of a man who had always seen, but was devoid of the sense of touch ; secondly, of a man in whom the senses of sight and touch were mutually contra- dictory. We might ask the former whether, if the missing sense were given him, or sight were obscured by a bandage, he would recognise bodies by touch. It is clear that geometry (provided he were acquainted with that science) would be an infallible guide as to whether the evidence of the two senses were contradictory or no. All he would have to do would be to take the cube or sphere in his hand, and demonstrate its properties, and pronounce that what he feels a cube is a cube to the eye ; hence it is a cube he holds. As to one who is ignorant of this science, I believe he would not more easily distinguish a cube from a sphere by touch than Molyneux' blind man distinguished them by sight. 140 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS In the case of a man in whom the sensations of sight and touch are in a perpetual contradiction, I do not know what he would think of shapes, order, symmetry, beauty, ugliness, etc. In all probability he would be with regard to those things as we are with regard to the real extension and real duration of beings. He would, in general, say that a body possesses a shape, but he must be inclined to think that it is neither that which he sees nor that which he feels. Such an one might be dissatisfied with his senses, but his senses would be neither satisfied nor dissatisfied with the objects. Were he inclined to charge one sense with inaccuracy, I imagine it would be touch. A hundred circumstances would incline him to think that the form of objects changes rather by the action of his hands upon them than by that of the objects on his eyes. But in conse- quence of these preconceived notions, the difference between hardness and softness which he would find in bodies would be very perplexing to him. But does It iollow that figures are better known to us because our senses are not self-contradictory ? Who has told us that they are not false witnesses ? Yet we pass judgment. Alas ! madam, when we weigh our human knowledge in Montaigne's scale we are almost reduced to adopting his motto. For what do we know ? What of the nature of matter ? Nothing. What of the nature of spirit and thought ? Still less. What of the nature of movement, space and duration ? Absolutely nothing. What of the truths of geometry ? Ask any honest mathema- THE LETTER ON THE BLIND 141 ticians, and they will own to you that all their pro- positions are identical, and that so many volumes upon the circle (for example) are nothing but repetitions by a hundred different methods that it is a figure where all the lines drawn from the centre to the circumference are equal. Thus we scarce know anything, yet what numbers of books there are whose authors have all pretended to know- ledge I I cannot think why the world is not tired of reading so much and learning nothing, unless it be for the very same reason that I have been talking to you for two hours, without being tired and with- out telling you anything. 1 With profound respect, I am, madam, Your very humble and obedient servant. 1 1 [This translation has been collated with an eighteenth-century translation, undated and anonymous, entitled a Letter on Blindness,] ADDITION TO THE PRECEDING LETTER 1 I AM going to jot down, anyhow, on paper, certain phenomena of which I was then ignorant, and which will serve as proofs or refutations of certain para- graphs in my Letter on the Blind. I wrote the latter thirty-three or thirty-four years ago, and I have re- read it without partiality, and am not entirely dis- satisfied with It. Although the first portion seemed to me more interesting than the second, and I felt that the former could have been further extended, the latter much abbreviated, I left both as I had written them, for fear that the young man's work might suffer by the old man's retouching. I think I should find it impossible to-day to emulate all that passes muster in ideas and in expression ; and I fear I am equally unable to correct what merits criticism. A famous contemporary painter spends the evening of his life in spoiling the master-pieces produced in his maturity. I know not if the defects he finds in them are real ; but either he never possessed the 1 ** We have appended to the Letter on the Blind 'the sequel which Diderot composed a long time after it. ... Those who accuse the writer of having always written hastily or of having always been hard and positive have certainly not read all his works. This sequel alon& would confute them." (Defting, B) 142 ADDITION TO THE PRECEDING 143 talent to improve them if he carried the imitation of nature to the extreme limits of art ; or, If he possessed it, he has lost it, for all human qualities perish as a man decays. There comes a time when taste gives counsels which are recognised as just, but which we are unable to follow. It is the weakness of spirit arising from the knowledge of weakness, or laziness which is one of the results of weakness and want of spirit, which stands in the way of a labour which would detract from the value of my work rather than improve it : Solve senescentem mature sanus equum^ fie peccet ad extremum ridendus^ et ilia ducat* 1 Horace, Epistolar^ lib. i, epist. i, v. S, 9. Phenomena I. An artist who Is both an enlightened student of the theory of his art, and unequalled in its practice, has assured me that it was by touch and not by sight that he judged of the soundness of kernels ; and that he rolled them gently between his thumb and first finger, and so discovered by successive im- pressions small inequalities of surface which were invisible to his eye. II. I have heard of a blind man who recognised by touch the colour of stuffs. III. I could name one who arranges the colours of bouquets with the taste upon which Jean Jacques 1 " You would be wise to turn loose the eld horse in good time, lest he fail in the end, amid laughter^ and strain himselfC" 1 144 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS Rousseau prided himself when, whether in jest or earnest, he confided to his friends his scheme for setting up a school to teach the flower-sellers of Paris. IV. At Amiens there was a blind dresser who presided over numerous workmen as well as if he had the gift of sight. V. In the case of one sighted man the use of his eyes destroyed his certainty of touch ; and in order to cut his hair, he removed the mirror and placed himself before a bare wall. The blind man who does not see a danger that threatens him is the more courageous, and I am sure he would walk with firmer step over the narrow and elastic planks bridging a precipice. There are very few who are undismayed by the sight of abysses beneath them. VI. Everyone has heard of the famous surgeon Daviel. 1 I was often present during his operations. He removed a cataract from the eyes of a blacksmith who had contracted this disease from exposure to the fire of his forge ; and during twenty-five years of blindness he had grown so accustomed to the guidance of touch that he had to be forced to use the sense which had been restored to him. Daviel would beat him and say, ' ' Use your eyes, you wretch!" He walked and moved, and did all that we do with our eyes open, with his eyes shut. 1 Jacques Daviel, surgeon, born in 1696. In 1728 he made a special study of diseases of the eye, and acquired such a high reputation for skill, that in the month of November 1752 alone he performed two hundred and twenty-six operations for cataract; of which one hundred and eighty- two were successful. He died in 1762. (A) ADDITION TO THE PRECEDING 145 We are drawn to the conclusion that the eye is not so necessary nor so essential to our happiness as we are inclined to believe. If the spectacle of nature had no charms for the blind smith Daviel operated on, what object is there to the loss of which we should be otherwise than indifferent, after long deprivation of sight accompanied by no pain ? The sight of a beloved woman? I don't believe it, in spite of the story I am going to relate. \Ve imagine that if one had passed a long time \\ ithout seeing, one would never be weary of looking ; but that is not the case. What a contrast between momentary and constant blindness ! VII. Poor patients seeking Daviel's help were drawn to his laboratory from all the provinces of the kingdom by his charity, and his reputation also gathered there a large body of interested and learned spectators. I believe Marmontel and I were present on the same day. The patient was seated and his cataract removed ; Daviel laid his hand upon the eyes which he had just restored to the light. An old woman, standing beside him, showed the liveliest interest in the success of the operation ; she shook in every limb at each movement of the operator. The latter signed to her to draw near, placed her kneeling opposite the patient, and removed his hands. The patient opened his eyes, saw, and cried : " Oh, it is my mother ! " I have never heard a more piteous cry ; I seem to hear it still. The old woman fainted, the spectators wept, and gave their money freely. 10 146 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS VIII. The most astonishing case of all those who have lost their sight almost from their infancy was Mademoiselle Melanie de Salignac, a relative of Monsieur de la Fargue, a lieutenant-general in the army, who recently 'died at the age of ninety-one, covered with wounds and honours. She was the daughter of Madame de Blacy, who is still living, and who never ceases to regret a child who was the deliglit of her life and the admiration of all her acquaintances. Madame de Blacy is a woman of high character, who is willing to confirm the truth of my account. I write from her dictation such par- ticulars of the life of Mademoiselle de Salignac as did not come under my personal observation during a friendship which began with her and her family in 1760, and which lasted until 1763, the year of her death. She had a sound judgment and great sweetness of disposition and subtlety of mind, as well as nai'vete and freshness. When an aunt asked her mother to help her entertain nineteen bores at dinner, she replied, " I do not understand my dear aunt : why be kind to nineteen bores ? I only wish to be kind to those I love." The sound of voices had the same attraction or antipathy for her as facial expression for those who see. A relation of hers, a receiver-general of finance, unexpectedly behaved badly to her family, and she said with astonishment : " Who would have believed i t of such a charming voice ? " When she heard singers, she distinguished between dark and fair voices. ADDITION TO THE PRECEDING 14; When people spoke to her, she judged of their height by the direction of the sound, which came to her from above if the person speaking were tall, and from below if that person was short. She was not anxious to see, and one day I asked her the reason. " The reason," she replied, \ and quadrille well. She sorted her cards herself, and recognised each by touch from minute peculiarities others could neither see nor feel. In reversis she had a special place for the ace (especially the ace of diamonds) and the knave of hearts. The only difference In playing with her was that the card played was named. If the knave of hearts was in danger, a smile passed over her face, which she could not restrain though she realised that it was indiscreet. She was a fatalist, and believed that our efforts to escape our destiny only served to draw us thither. I do not know what she thought of religion ; she kept her opinions to herself out of consideration for her mother, who was devout. Lastly, I will give you her ideas upon hand- writing, drawing, engraving, and painting, and they are, I think, very just, as I hope you will think after reading the following conversation between us. She begins the dialogue : ct If you trace on my hand with a point, a nose, a mouth, a man, a woman, or a tree, I should be sure to recognise them ; and if the tracing was correct, I should hope to recognise the person whom you had drawn ; my hand would become a sensitive mirror, but the difference in sensibility between this hand and the organ of sight Is Immense. I suppose the eye is a living canvas of infinite delicacy ; the air strikes the object, and is reflected back from the 156 DIDEROT S PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS object to the eye, which receives a multitude of im- pressions varying in accordance with the nature, the form, the colour of the object, and also' perhaps with the properties of the air which I do not know, and of which you are equally ignorant ; and the object is represented to you by the variety of these sensations. ** If the skin of my hand was as sensitive as your eye, I should see with my hand as you see with your eyes ; and I sometimes imagine there are animals who have no eyes, but can nevertheless see. " "And the mirror?" "If any bodies are not mirrors, it is by some defect in their composition which destroys the re- flection of the air. I think this is the more likely as gold, silver, iron, and copper, when polished, are able to reflect the air, while rough water and cracked ice lose this property. Variety in sensation (and hence in the property of reflecting air), in the materials you employ, distinguishes the writing from the drawing, the drawing from the engraving, the engraving from the picture. The writing, the drawing, the engraving, and the picture in one colour are all monochromes." " But if there is only one colour, we should only distinguish that colour. " " It seems that the surface of the canvas, the depth of colour, and the way in which it is used, produce in the reflection of the air a corresponding variation to that of the objects. Don't ask me any more, for that is all I know." ADDITION TO THE PRECEDING 157 " To try to teach you any more would be waste of time." I have not described in her case all I might have noticed if I had seen her oftener and questioned her skilfully. I give you my word of honour that all I have recorded is actual fact. She died at the age of twenty-two. \Vith a wonderful memory, and strength of mind as wonder- ful, what progress she would have made in science if she had had a longer life I Her mother read history to her, and this was a task pleasant and useful to both of them. LETTER ON THE DEAF AND DUMB Letter to Monsieur - . 1751. I AM sending, sir, to the author of The Fine Arts reduced to a Single Principle, the Letter revised, corrected, and augmented in accordance with the advice of my friends ; but always with the same title. I grant that this title is applicable equally to the large number of those who speak without under- standing and the small number of those who under- stand without speaking, and to the very small number of those who speak and understand, and for whose use my letter is solely intended. I admit that it is an imitation of another Letter 1 which might be better ; but I am tired of hunting for a better title. Whatever importance you attri- bute to the choice of a title, the title of my letter will remain unchanged. I do not like quotations, and I like Greek quota- tions least of all ; they give a learned air to a book, which is no longer fashionable. They frighten away readers, and if I was deciding from a publisher's 1 Letter on the Blinds/or the Use of those -who See. (D) 158 LETTER ON THE DEAF AND DUMB 159 standpoint I should leave out such scarecrows. But I am not a publisher, so please suffer the Greek quotations to remain where I have placed them. If you care less for a book being good, than that it should be read, I do not agree with you ; what I care for is to make a good book, although it may risk being less read. As to the number of subjects I touch upon moving from one to another, I would have you know, and tell others, that this is no fault in a letter where one is allowed to converse freely, and where the last word of a phrase is a sufficient link to the next You may therefore print me, if that is all ; but print me anonymously, if you please. I can always admit the authorship later. I know one to whom people would not attribute it, and another on whom it would be certainly fathered, if it possessed some eccentricity in its ideas, some share of imagination, style, some temerity of thought which I should be sorry to share, a fine display of mathematics, meta- physics, Italian and English ; less Latin and Greek, and more music. See that no errors creep into the text ; a single mistake is enough to ruin all. You will find in Havercamp's fine edition of Lucretius in the last book the figure I want. Take out the child which half hides her, imagine a wound beneath the breast, and have it copied. My friend Monsieur de S. has undertaken to revise the proofs. His address is ... I am, etc. 160 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS LETTER ON THE DEAF AND DUMB FOR THE USE OF THOSE WHO HEAR AND SPEAK: Which treats of the origin of inversions in language, of harmony of style, of sublimity of situation, and of some advan- tages which the French language has over most ancient and modern languages, also some thoughts on expression in the fine arts. I HAD no intention, sir, to take credit for your researches, and you may claim what you please in this letter. If it happens that my ideas are similar to yours, I am like the ivy which mingles its foliage with the oak. I might have addressed my letter to the Abbe de Condillac, or to Monsieur du Marsais, who has also treated of inversions ; but you just came to my mind, and I have made free with you, for I am persuaded that the public will not this time take a happy accident for a deliberate choice. My only fear is, that I may waste your time and snatch from you those hours which you are doubt- less devoting to philosophy, and which you owe to that study. Now, in order to treat of inversions we must first consider how languages are formed. Objects that strike the senses are those that are first noticed, and those which unite various qualities which strike the senses are named first, *.*. the different objects of which the world is composed Then the various qualities are distinguished and named, and these form most of our adjectives. Afterwards, these sensible LETTER ON THE DEAF AND DUMB 161 qualities being put aside, some common quality was observed in various objects, such as impenetrability, extension, colour, shape, etc. , and from these abstract and general names were formed and nearly all sub- stantives. Gradually men became accustomed to think that all these names represented real things ; and the sensible qualities were regarded as simple accidents, and thus the adjective was thought to be subordinate to the substantive, although the sub- stantive does not really exist and the adjective is everything. If you are asked to describe an object, you answer that it is a body with a surface, im- penetrable, shaped, coloured, and movable. But subtract all these adjectives from your definition and what is left of that imaginary being you call a body ? If you wished to arrange the terms of your definition in their natural order, you would say a coloured, shaped, extended, impenetrable, movable substance. It seems to me that a man seeing the object for the first time would be affected by the different qualities in this order of terms. The eye would be first struck by the shape, colour, and surface ; touch would then discover its impenetrability, and eye and touch together would discover its mobility. There would, therefore, be no inversion in this definition, and there is an inversion in the definition in its first form. It follows, therefore, that if we wish to maintain that there is no inversion in the French language, or at least that it is much rarer than In the learned tongues, the utmost we can say is that our constructions in French are for the most ii 162 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS part uniform ; that the substantive is always, or nearly always, placed before the adjective ; and the verb between them. For if we consider the question on its own merits, and ask if the adjective should be placed before or after the noun, it will appear that we frequently reverse the natural order of ideas. The example I have just given is an in- stance of this. I say the natural order of ideas ; for we should distinguish here between the natural order and the acquired^ or what we may term the scientific order ; the latter is a deliberate arrange- ment after a language is fully formed. As adjectives usually represent sensible qualities, they stand first in the natural order of ideas ; but to a philosopher, or rather to philosophers who are accustomed to regard abstract substantives as realities, substantives will come first in the scientific order, being, in their language, the support which upholds the adjective. Thus of the two definitions of a, body I gave, the first follows the scientific or acquired, the second the natural order. From this we may conclude that it is perhaps owing to the peripatetic philosophy, which realised all general and abstract entities, that we have in our language hardly any of what we call inversions in the classics. Our Gallic authors had much more than we have, and this philosophy was in the ascendant while our language was being perfected under Louis XIII and Louis XIV. The Ancients, who generalised less, and who studied nature more in detail, were less monotonous in the order of their LETTER ON THE DEAF AND DUMB 163 tongue, and the word inversion would have perhaps astonished them. You will not raise as an objection here, that the peripatetic philosophy is Aristotle's philosophy, and hence the philosophy of some portion of the Ancients, for you doubtless tell your disciples that our peripatetic philosophy is very different from Aristotle's. But it is, perhaps, unnecessary to go back as far as the creation of the world and the origin of language to explain why inversions crept into and were preserved in languages. It would be sufficient to make an imaginary journey to a people whose language one was unacquainted with ; or, what comes to almost the same thing, to experiment with a man who would forgo the use of articulate sounds and try to make himself understood by gestures alone. Such a man, who would perfectly understand the questions put to him, would be an excellent subject for experiment ; and from the succession of his gestures definite inferences could be drawn as to the order of ideas which seemed good to the early men in order to communicate their thoughts by gestures, and under what circumstances articulate sounds were invented I should give my " theoretical mute" plenty of time to compose his replies ; and as to the questions, I would make a point of introducing ideas whose expression by means of gesture I should be most anxious to learn. It would be both useful and entertaining to multiply experiments upon these ideas, and to propound the same questions to a 1 64 DIDEROT 'S PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS number of persons at once. I believe that a philo- sopher who practised such experiments with some friends, who were intelligent men and good logicians, would not find it a total waste of time. An Aristo- phanes would no doubt turn it to ridicule, but what matter ? One could say what Zeno said to his dis- ciple : ci (pi\ocro? /carayeXa&fcroVei'o?, w?, etc. If you wish to become a philosopher, expect to be ridiculed. That is a fine maxim, sir, and one that would elevate souls less courageous than ours above human comment and all frivolous considerations. You must not confuse the experiment I suggest with ordinary pantomime. To translate an action and a speech into gesture are two very different things. I am sure that there are inversions in the language of our mutes, that each one has his style, and that their inversions denote differences as pro- nounced as those we find in ancient Greek and Latin authors. But as we always most highly approve of our own style, the discussion that would ensue after these experiments would be of the most lively and philosophical nature, for all our theoretical mutes, when they had leave to use their tongues again, would be obliged to justify not only their expres- sion, but also the way they placed such and such an idea in a certain order in their gestures. This leads me to another idea that is a little alien to the subject of my letter, but in a letter digres- sions are allowed, especially when they lead to useful results. My idea would be to analyse, as it LETTER ON THE DEAF AND DUMB 165 were, a man, and to examine what he derives from each of his senses. 1 have sometimes amused myself with this kind of metaphysical anatomy, and I consider that of all the senses the eye was the most superficial, the ear the proudest, smell the most voluptuous, taste the profoundest and most philosophical. It would be amusing to get together a society, of which each should have only one sense ; there can be no doubt that all these persons would look on one another as out of his wits, and I leave you to judge with what reason. And yet this is an example of what happens amongst us every day ; we have, so to speak, only one sense, and we judge of everything. We may remark that this group of five persons, each possessing only one sense, might by their faculty of abstraction have one interest in common that of geometry, and might understand one another on that subject, and that alone. But to return to our theoretical mutes, and to the questions we should put them. If these questions were such that more than one answer was possible, it would follow that one mute would give one, and another mute another ; and that the comparison between their replies would become impossible or at any rate difficult This difficulty suggested to me that a speech for transla- tion from French to gesture-language would be better than a question for experimental purposes. The translators must be warned to avoid ellipsis, for the language of gesture is difficult enough without increasing its laconism by the use of this figure. 1 66 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS By the efforts of those born deaf and dumb to make themselves understood, we see they express all they are able to express. I should therefore recommend our theoretical mutes to copy them, and, as far as is possible, to form no sentence where the subject and the attribute with all their depen- dencies are not expressed. In short, they would only be allowed the choice of the order in which they would present ideas, or rather the gestures representing these ideas. But there I see a difficulty. As thoughts, I know not by what contrivance, enter our mind very much in the form in which they appear in speech when they are tricked up, it is possible that this will cause some difficulty to our theoretical mutes ; perhaps they would be tempted to imitate the order of the words in the spoken language they are already familiar with a temptation which assails almost everyone who writes in a foreign language. All of our best modern Latinists fall into French constructions, so that perhaps our mutes' construc- tion will not be the construction of a man who had never had any notion of speech. What do you say ? Perhaps this difficulty would be of less frequent occurrence if our theoretical mutes were philosophers or orators ; but if this obstacle arises we might have recourse to one born deaf and dumb. You will doubtless think this a singular way of obtaining true notions of the formation of a language. But pray consider, how much less far from truth ignorance is than prejudice, and that a LETTER ON THE DEAF AND DUMB 167 man born deaf and dumb has no prejudices with regard to the manner of communicating his thoughts. Consider that inversions have not passed into his language from another, and that if he uses them it is nature alone which suggests their use ; that he is closely analogous to those beings people have imagined who with no trace of education, very few perceptions, and almost no memory, might easily pass for two-footed or four-footed animals. I can assure you, sir, that a translation of this gesture language would do the translator great credit, for not only must he have completely under- stood the meaning and the thought, but the order of the words of the translation must faithfully follow the order of the gestures of the original. (To do this a philosopher would have to question his author, hear his replies, and represent them with exactness ; but philosophy is not learnt in a day.) One of these requisites would, however, facilitate the rest ; and if the question was given with a precise explanation of the gestures which are to compose the answer, it would be possible to represent ges- tures as far as possible by words. I say as far as possible, for there are gestures so sublime that the noblest eloquence can never translate them. Such is the scene in Shakespeare's tragedy of Macbeth. Lady Macbeth, walking in her sleep, advances silently with closed eyes (Act v, Scene i), and rubbing her hands together as if she were washing away the stain of the king's blood she had shed twenty years before, I know nothing in speech so 1 68 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS pathetic as the silence and motion of this woman's hands. What an expression of remorse ! The way in which another woman carried the tidings of his death to her husband, who was still uncertain of his fate, is another example of a gesture unapproached In its vigour by the spoken word. She went with her son in her arms to a spot in the country which her husband could see from the tower in which he was imprisoned ; and, after looking for some time at the tower, she took a handful of earth which she scattered in the form of a cross on the body of her son, whom she had laid at her feet Her husband understood the sign, and starved himself to death. The sublimest thought Is forgotten, but these actions are never effaced from one's memory. I could make many reflections at this point on sublimity of situation, but they would take me too far from my subject. Many of the fine lines in that magnificent scene in fferaclius, where Phocas does not know which of the two princes is his son, have been justly admired. For my part, the passage in the scene that I prefer is that where the tyrant turns to each of the princes in turn, and calls them by the name of his son, and they both remain cold and motionless : * ' Martian^ d ce mot aucun ne veut rtpondre* " x This cannot be put upon paper, and gesture here triumphs over speech. Epaminondas, at the battle "of Mantinaea, is 1 [" Martian 1 and none will answer to the word." -Corneille, st Act iv, Scene iv.] LETTER ON THE DEAF AND DUMB 169 mortally wounded ; the doctors tell him he will die when the spear is drawn from his body. He asks for. his shield, for it is dishonourable to lose the shield in battle ; and when this is brought to him, he draws out the spear-head himself. In the sublime scene at the close of the tragedy of Rhodogune, the most effective moment is certainly when Antiochus lifts the bowl to his lips, and Timagene enters crying " Ah, lord !" (Act v, Scene iv). What a throng of ideas and emotions crowd upon the audience at this gesture and this cry ! But I am digressing. To come back to our man born deaf and mute, I know of one who would be useful for experimental purposes, because he is intelligent and has expressive gestures, as you shall see. I was playing chess one day, and the dumb man was watching. My opponent fought me to a difficult position, and the dumb man quite understood, and, thinking the game was lost, he closed his eyes, drooped his head, and let fall his arms as a sign that he considered me checkmated, or done for. Consider for a moment how metaphorical is the language of gesture. At first I thought as he did ; but as I had not exhausted the combinations, I was in no hurry to yield, and I looked about for a way out. The dumb man still thought there was none, and he expressed this very clearly by shaking his head and by putting back the lost pieces in the box. His example induced the other spectators to discuss the situation ; they examined it, and, after some fruitless expedients had been tried, a successful one 170 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS was discovered. I made use of it, and explained to the dumb man that he was mistaken, and that I had escaped though he did not expect me to. But he, by pointing his finger at the spectators one after another, and making a motion of the lips, accom- panied by a sweeping movement of his arms in the direction of the door and the tables, replied that it was no credit to me to have got out of my difficulty by calling in all and sundry to my help. His gestures were so significant that no one could mis- understand him, and the popular expression "all and sundry " * occurred to many at the same time : this expression was definitely translated by our dumb man's gestures. You know, at least you have heard, of a singular machine with which the inventor proposed to give sonatas in colour. I thought that if anyone could appreciate a performance of ocular music, and could judge of it without prejudice, it would be a man born deaf and dumb. I therefore took my friend to the house in the rue St Jacques, where the operator and the machine with colours was exhibited. Ah, sir, you would never guess the kind of impression that it made on him, nor the ideas it suggested. You see that it was impossible to explain to him beforehand the nature and marvellous powers of the harpsichord; and, having no idea of sound, this instru- ment with colours could not suggest to him any musical impressions. The purpose of the machine 1 [Consumer le fiers, le qitart ct Us peasants; literally, "the third, the quarter, and the passers-by."] LETTER ON THE DEAF AND DUMB 171 was as incomprehensible to him as the use of our organs of speech. What, then, were his thoughts, and what was the cause of his admiration for Father CastePs coloured fans? Guess, sir, his conjectures about this ingenious machine, 1 which very few people have seen, though many have talked about it, and whose invention would do honour to many of those who ridicule it. Our deaf-and-dumb friend imagined that the inventor was also deaf and dumb, and that his harpsichord was the instrument by which he com- municated with other men ; he imagined also that each shade of colour represented a letter of the alphabet, and that by touching the keys rapidly he combined these letters into words and phrases, and, in fact, spoke in colours. You may imagine he was pleased with his own perspicacity in finding this out ; but our friend did not rest on his laurels ; the idea suddenly came into his head that he now grasped what music and musical instruments were. He supposed that music was a peculiar manner of communicating thought, and that musical instruments lutes, violins, and trumpets were so many different organs of speech. You will say that only a man who had never heard music or a musical instrument could have happened on such a theory. But please consider that this theory, although obviously false to you, seemed almost proved to a deaf-and-dumb person. When the deaf- 1 [Voltaire ridiculed the machine invented by the Jesuit CastcL Diderot, on the other hand, returned to the idea again and again, and ^mentions it in the Encycfotos&a. (A)] 172 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS and-dumb man calls to mind the attention he has observed us pay to music and to musicians, and the evidences of joy or grief depicted on our countenances and in our gestures as we listen to beautiful music, and when he compares them with the similar effects produced by speech or by visible objects, he cannot imagine that music has no definite meaning and that vocal and instrumental music arouses in us no distinct impressions. And is not this, sir, an exact symbol of the way in which we form ideas, our theories, and, in a word, the conceptions by which so many philosophers have won fame? Whenever they attempt to explain matters which seem to demand another organ which is lacking before they can be completely understood, they have often shown less penetration and have wandered further from the truth than the deaf mute I have been describing ; for, after all, if we do not express our thoughts as distinctly by means of musical instruments as with our lips, and if musical notes do not convey our ideas as distinctly as speech, yet they do convey something. The blind man I described in the Letter on the Blind' 1 assuredly displayed great penetration in his conception of the use of the telescope and spectacles, and his definition of a mirror is very remarkable ; but there is more profundity and truth in my deaf- mute's notion of Father CasteFs harpsichord and of our music and musical instruments. Even if he did not hit upon the exact truth, he hit upon a great 1 See Letter on the Blind, pp. 72-73. LETTER ON THE DEAF AND DUMB 173 possibility. This penetration will surprise you less, perhaps, if you fancy that everyone who walks through a picture gallery is really unconsciously acting the part of a deaf man who is amusing him- self by examining the dumb who are conversing on subjects familiar to him. This is one of the points of view with which I always look at pictures ; and I fancy it a sure means of divining ambiguous actions and equivocal movements ; of being at once aware of the frigidity and confusion of an ill-arranged action or of conversation ; and of seeing at once, in a scene rendered in painting, all the faults of languid or exaggerated acting. The term " acting " which I have just used, because it expresses what I mean, calls to my mind another mode of studying which I often employed and which taught me more about actions and gestures than all the books in the world. I used to frequent the theatre, and 1 knew by heart most of our best plays. On the days when I meant to examine actions and gestures I would climb to the gallery, for the further I was from the actors the better. As soon as the curtain was raised, and the rest of the audience disposed themselves to listen, I put my fingers in my ears, much to the astonishment of my neighbours ; not knowing my motives, they looked on me as a madman who only came to the play to miss it. I paid no attention to their remarks, and kept my fingers obstinately in my ears as long as the gestures and actions of the actor corresponded with the dialogue which I remembered. When I was 174 D1DEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS puzzled by the gestures I took my fingers from my ears and listened. Ah, how few actors there are who can stand such a test, and how humiliated the majority would be if I were to give the world my criticisms ! But judge of my neighbours' surprise when they saw me shed tears at the pathetic passages, though I had my fingers in my ears. That was too much for them, and even the least inquisitive began to question me. But I coolly answered that * ' everybody had his own way of listening, and mine was to shut my ears to hear the better," and found some silent amusement in the comments caused by my real or apparent eccen- tricity and in the simplicity of some young people who also tried putting their fingers in their ears to hear as I did, and were surprised at their lack of success. Whatever you may think of my expedient, pray consider that if, to judge correctly of intonation, we must listen to an actor without looking at him, it is very natural to watch an actor without hear- ing him, if we are to judge correctly of his gestures and action. I may add that the celebrated writer of plays, Le Sage, the author of The Lame Devil, The BacJielor of Salamanca, Gil Bias of Santillana, Turcaret^ and a number of plays and comic operas in which his son, the inimitable Montmeny, took part, became so deaf in his old age that people had to shout into his ear-trumpet. Yet he was in the habit of frequenting the theatre to see his pieces played, and could follow them almost word for LETTER ON THE DEAF AND DUMB 175 word ; indeed, he said he was a better judge of his plays and their action when he could no longer hear the actors ; and I am certain, from my own personal experience, that he was right. In studying gesture language it appears to me the principal idea should be presented first, because it throws light on the rest as indicating what the succeeding gestures refer to. When the subject of a proposition in oratory or gesticulation is not announced, the significance of the other gestures or words remains uncertain. This is certainly the case in Greek or Latin phrases, but not in the language of gesture when properly constructed. Suppose I am at table with a deaf-mute, and he wishes to tell his servant to give me some wine. He first beckons to his servant, then looks at me, then he imitates the action of a man pouring out wine. In this sentence it hardly matters which of the last two signs comes first : the deaf mute, after beckoning to his servant, may either begin with the sign representing his order or that denoting the person whom the order concerns ; but the position of the first gesture cannot be altered. Only an illogical mute could displace it. For this displacement would be as absurd as a man speaking without knowing whom he was addressing. As to the order of the two other gestures, it is a matter of taste, fancy, suitability, and harmony of style, and does not affect the sense. As a rule, the more ideas there are in a sentence, and the more possible arrangement of gestures or other signs there are, the greater 176 DIDEROT S PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS danger of falling into contradictions, ambiguities, and other faults of construction. I do not know if we can justly estimate a man's opinions and morals by his writings, but I think we can form a good judgment of his intellectual abilities from his style, or rather his manner of constructing sentences. I can at least say that I have never found myself mistaken in my judgment. I have observed that every writer whose sentences had to be completely re- written would also have required an entirely new brain before he was fit for anything. But how is it possible in a dead language to use correct constructions when there are so many pos- sible ways of arranging words? Our language is so simple and uniform that I venture to say it will be easier to write and speak French correctly, if it were to die, than it is possible to write Latin and Greek now. How many inversions do we use to-day in Latin and Greek which would not have been permitted in the days of Cicero and Demos- thenes and which the refined ears of those orators would have rejected ? But, people will tell me, have we not in our language adjectives which are only used before a substantive, and others which are only used after ? How can our posterity learn these fine distinctions ? Reading good authors is not enough. I agree with you ; and if the French language dies, future savants, who care enough for our literature to learn and write our language, will be sure to write indifferently blanc bonnet or bonnet blanc^ ml chant auteur or auteur LETTER ON THE DEAF AND DUMB 177 m chant, homme galant and galant homme, and a vast number of similar phrases which would make non- sense of their writings were we to rise up to read them, but which would not prevent their ignorant contemporaries from exclaiming when they read some such piece : {< Racine did not write more correctly/' or " That is just like Despreaux ; Bossuet could not have said it better ; this prose has the music, the force, the elegance and ease of Voltaire's. " But if a limited number of difficulties may cause those who come after us to stumble, what are we to think of our modern Greek and Latin authors and of the admiration they obtain? In talking to a deaf-mute it is found to be almost impossible to describe to him indefinite portions of quantity, number, space, or time, or to make him grasp any abstract idea. One can never be sure that he realises the difference in tense between I made, I have made, I was making, and / should have made. It is the same with conditional propositions. If, then, I was right in saying that at the origin of language men first named the principal objects of sense, such as fruit, water, trees, animals, serpents, etc., and then named passions, places, and persons, qualities, seasons, etc., I may add that signs for periods of time and tenses were invented last of all. I imagine that for long centuries men had no other tenses than the present indicative and the infinitive, which became, according to the circumstances, either a future or a past. I am supported in this conjecture by the present 12 i/8 DIDEROT'S PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS state of the lingua franca the language spoken by the various Christian nations trading with Turkey and the Levant ports. I believe it is the same to- day that it has always been, and that it will never develop. Its base is a corrupt Italian. The present infinitive is used for every tense, and its meaning is modified by guessing and by the other words of the sentence. Thus, / love thee, I was loving thee, I shall love thee, are all in lingua franca, "miamarti." All have sung, Let each one sing, All will sing, are ' ' tutti cantara. " / wish, I was wishing, I have 'wished, I should like to marry you, are "mi voleri sposarti* " I imagine that inversions have crept into a language and been preserved in it because gesture language gave rise to the language of oratory, and that they naturally retained the position thus as- signed to them in the sentence. I also think that, for the same reason, as tense was not accurately defined even after conjunctions were formed, some languages, like Hebrew, which has no present or imperfect, did without certain tenses. They said Credidi propter quod locutus sum instead of Credo et ideo loquor: I Jiave believed, and therefore I have spoken, instead of / believe, and therefore I speak. In other languages the same tense had two different meanings, as in the Greek language, where the aorist is at one time expressive of the present, at another of the past. Let me quote as an illustra- tion there are many others a passage in the EncJuridion, which is perhaps not so familiar to you LETTER ON THE DEAF AND DUMB 179 as some. Epictetus says : QeXovcri KOL avrol L\O- ay/xa ' efra KOL Trjv a-eavrov vviv /cara/^aSe, el Svvaa-ai ftaa-Tdarai. TLevTaOXog etvat f3ou\et, rj TraXai 0-7-779 ; tSe a-eavrov TOVS /3paxiova$, TOI/? fjLrjpovs, Ttjv 6vv /cara- jj.aQe (ch. xxix). A close translation is : " These men also wish to be philosophers ; O man, first have learnt what it is that you wish to be, have studied your strength and the burden, have considered your arms and thighs, have tried your loins if you intend to be a pentathlete or a wrestler." This can be much better translated by substituting the present for the first and second aorists ; thus : "These men also wish to be philosophers. Man, first learn what it is you wish to be ; .study your strength, and the burden ; consider your arms and thighs ; try your loins if you intend to be a pentathlete or a wrestler. " The pentathlete, as you know, was one who intended to enter for all the gymnastic exercises. I consider these eccentricities of tense as the result of the original imperfection of languages and the traces of their original rudimentary state, against which common sense (which does not allow one and the same expression to render different ideas) vainly strove in after times. It was in vain ; the usage was fixed, and use won a victory over common sense. But there was, perhaps, not a single Latin and Greek author who was aware of this defect. I go further, and .maintain that every Greek and Latin author probably imagined in their speeches and writings that their words exactly i8o DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS followed the order of their ideas. But evidently it was not so. When Cicero begins his oration pro Marcello by Diuturni silentii, Patres conscripti, quo eram his temporibus usus, etc., we can see that he was thinking of something before his c ' long silence " an idea which was to follow and break in upon his "long silence," and which caused him to say Diuturnt silentii instead of Diuturnum silentium. This remark upon the inversion of the beginning of this oration applies equally to all cases of inversion ; as a rule, in all Greek and Latin periods, however long they may be, we observe at once that the writer had some reason for preferring to use certain cases, and that there was not the same inversion in his ideas as in the order of his words. In the above sentence of Cicero's, what made him use the genitive case in Diuturni silentii^ the ablative in quo y the imperfect tense m eram, and so on, was the order of ideas pre-existing in his mind which did not coincide with the order of the words an order he obeyed unconsciously, from a long practice in trans- position. Why should Cicero not have used in- version unconsciously, since we, who think our language follows the natural order of ideas, do so too? I was therefore justified in distinguishing between the natural and the acquired or scientific order of ideas and signs. You thought, sir, it might be argued, that there was no inversion in that period of Cicero's ; you are mistaken, but two considerations which have escaped your notice will convince you. The first is, that as LETTER ON THE DEAF AND DUMB 181 inversion proper, or the acquired, scientific and gram- matical order, is really an order in words which does not correspond to the order in ideas, what is inver- sion for one is not so for another, for different minds may put their words in different order. For in- stance, in the sentence serpent em fuge I would ask you which is the principal idea. You may say that it is the serpent, but another will say it is flight ; and both ot you may be right. A timid man thinks only of the serpent ; but the man who fears my danger more than he fears the serpent thinks only of my flight : one is overwhelmed by terror, the other gives me warning. The second thing I would remark is, that when we are presenting a series of ideas to others, and the main idea we wish to im- press upon them is not the one by which we our- selves are most impressed (because we and our hearers are differently situated), it is this former idea which we should present first, and such an in- version is but a matter of oratory. Let us apply these observations to the first period of the oration $ro Marcello. I picture to myself Cicero mounting the tribune to speak to the people ; and I see that the first idea that will strike his audience is that it is a long time since he spoke to them ; hence diulurni silentii, his prolonged silence, is the first idea he must present to them, although the principal idea in his mind is rather hodiernus dies finem attulit ; for the orator's main preoccupation is the speech he is about to make, not his past silence. I notice another reason for the use of the genitive case in diuturni silentii ; 1 82 DIDEROT 'S PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS the audience could not realise the fact of Cicero's prolonged silence without seeking for the cause of it, and why he was at last breaking it. Now the genitive, being a case incomplete in itself, induces the minds of his hearers to travel onwards to meet the ideas that the orator could not present at once. These are, sir, the remarks upon the passage in question which you might have made. I am sure Cicero would have arranged this period quite differently, if, instead of speaking at Rome, he had been suddenly transported to Africa to plead at Carthage. This will show that what was not an inversion for Cicero's hearers would be and must be one for the orator himself. But to go a little further: I hold that when a phrase only contains very few ideas, it is very diffi- cult to determine the natural order of these ideas in relation to the speaker ; for if they are not all pre- sented at once, their succession is so rapid that it is often impossible to decide which strikes us first. Who can say if the mind cannot embrace a certain number at one and the same instant ? Perhaps you will call this paradoxical ; but let us examine to- gether how the article 7#V, tlle y le came to be intro- duced into Latin and into our language. It will not be a long .or difficult matter, and may induce you to accept a position that you find distasteful at present. Let us first transport ourselves to the period when Latin adjectives and substantives which denoted the qualities perceived by sense in various natural objects LETTER ON THE DEAF AND DUMB 183 were almost all invented, but when no expression had yet been found for those intellectual subtilties which philosophy has even to-day much difficulty in distinguishing. Next imagine two hungry men, one of whom could see no food, while the other stood beneath a tree so very tall that he could not reach its fruit. Their sensations make both these men speak ; the first would say : / am hungry, I would like to eat ; and the second, What beautiful fruit / / am hungry ', I would like to eat. Now, it is obvious that the former has adequately expressed in words all that passed in his mind ; while the latter has left something unexpressed a portion of his thought must be supplied. The expression I would like to eat, when no food is to be seen, applies generally to all food that could appease hunger ; but the same expression is limited in its application, and refers only to a fine fruit when that fruit is to be seen. Thus, though they both said 7 am hungry, I would like to eat, the man who exclaimed "What a fine fruit ! " returned in thought to this fruit, and I make no doubt that if the article le had been in use he would have said : WJiat fine fruit ! I am hungry ; I would like to eat this (or this I would like to eat). The article le or celuim this case and in other similar cases denotes that the mind reverts to an object which it had previously considered, and the inven- tion of this symbol is, I think, a proof of the progress of the mind. Do not raise difficulties about the position this word ought to occupy in the sentence in accordance 1 84 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS with the natural order of ideas, for though these statements, What fine fruit ! I am hungry, I would like to eat that, are each expressed by two or three words, each only denotes a single notion ; the mid- most sentence, I am Iwngry, is expressed in Latin by a single word esurio. The fruit and its quality are perceived at the same time ; and when a Roman said esurio he only imagined he was expressing a single idea. / would much like to eat that are only modes of single sensation. / denotes the person who experiences it ; would like to eat, the desire and the nature of the sensation experienced ; much, its intensity ; it, the presence of the desired object But in the mind there is not the successive development we observe in speech ; if it had twenty mouths, and each mouth able to say a word, all the above ideas would be expressed at once. This could be ex- cellently executed on Father Castel's harpsichord, if our dumb friend's theory were in practice and each colour combined to form words. No tongue would approach it in the rapidity of its speech. But as we have not many mouths, people have attached several ideas to a single term. If there were more of these vigorous terms, instead of the tongue panting after the mind, such a number of ideas could be expressed at once that the mind would lag after the tongue which hastened in advance of it. What would then be the fate of inversion, which implies a disintegration of many simultaneous mental impressions and a number of words? Al- though we have few words equivalent to a long LETTER ON THE DEAF AND DUMB 185 speech, we have some, and Greek and Latin are full of them ; they are at once understood when used, and this is a proof that the mind experiences a multitude of sensations, if not simultaneously, yet in such rapid succession that it is impossible to distinguish their order. If I had to explain this system of the human understanding to one who found it difficult to grasp abstract ideas, I should say, "Consider man as a walking clock ; the heart as its mainspring, the contents of the thorax as the principal parts of the works ; look on the head as a bell furnished with little hammers attached to an infinite number of threads which are carried to all corners of the clock- case. Fix upon the bell one of those little figures with which we ornament the top of our clocks, and let it listen, like a musician who listens to see if his instrument is in tune : this little figure is the soul. If many of these little threads are pulled at once, the bell will be struck several times, and the little figure will hear several notes simultaneously. Imagine that there are some of these threads that are always being pulled ; and just as we only notice the noise of Paris by day when it ceases at night, we shall be unconscious of some sensations which are continuous, such as of our existence. The mind, especially in health, is unconscious of its own existence, unless it deliberately examines Itself. When we are well, we are unconscious of any part of our body ; and if any part draws attention to itself by pain, we are certainly not well ; and if it is by a pleasurable 186 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS sensation, it is by no means certain that we are the better for it." I could pursue my analogy still further, and add that the sounds produced by the bell do not die away at once, but have some duration ; that they produce chords with the sounds that follow, and the little figure that listens compares them, and pronounces them harmonious or dissonant ; that memory, which we need to form opinions and to speak, is the resonance of the bell ; the judgment, the formation of chords ; and speech, a succession of chords. It is not without reason that some brains are said to be "cracked," like a bell. And is not the law, which is so necessary in a series of harmonies, of having at least one note common to the chord and that following it, also applicable? Does not this common note resemble the middle term of a syllogism ? And what else is the likeness we observe in certain minds but the result of some freak of nature by which two intervals are marked, one a fifth and the other a third, in relation to another note? By this fertile analogy, and with all the madness of Pythagoras, I might demonstrate the wisdom of that Scythian law which prescribed one friend as a necessity, permitted two, and forbade three. Among the Scythians, I might say, a man was "out of tune" if the note which he gave forth found no harmonic among his fellow-men ; three friends would make a perfect accord ; while a fourth superadded would be but a repetition of one of the former three, or would introduce a discordant note, ' LETTER ON THE DEAF AND DUMB 187 But enough of this language of metaphor, which at best is but fitted to amuse and arrest the volatile mind of a child ; let us come back to philosophy, which requires arguments and not analogies. When people examined the various utterances called forth by the sensations of hunger and thirst, they observed that the same terms were used to express different notions ; and the symbols you y he, me, the, and many others, were invented for the sake of precision. A mental state during an indivisible moment of time was expressed by a number of words which divided the complete expression into a number of parts ; and because these words were uttered one after another, and were only understood in the order they were spoken, it was thought that the sensations they expressed were experienced by the mind in the same order. But this is not the case. Our mental state is one thing, our analysis of it quite another. This is so, whether we analyse it to ourselves or to others. The complete and instantaneous perception of this state is one thing ; the detailed and continuous effort of attention we make to analyse it, state it, and explain it to others, another. Our mind is a moving scene, which we are perpetually copying. We spend a great deal of time in rendering it faith- fully ; but the original exists as a complete whole, for the mind does not proceed step by step, like expression. The brush takes time to represent what the artist's eye sees in an instant In the growth of language, decomposition was a necessity ; but to see an object, to admire it, to experience an 1 88 D1DEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS agreeable sensation, and to desire to possess it, is but an instantaneous emotion, rendered in Greek and Latin by a single word. This word once uttered, all is said and understood. Ah, how our understand- ing is modified by words, and how cold a copy of reality is the most vigorous utterance ! Les ronces degouttantes Portent de ses cheveux les depouilles sanglantes. 1 This is one of the most life-like pictures I know, but yet how far is it from my imagination I I beg of you, sir, to consider these points if you wish for a juster notion of this complex question of inversion. For my part, I am fitter to gather a cloud than to scatter it, to suspend my judgment than to give a verdict ; and I am going to prove that if the paradox that I have just advanced does not hold good, and if our mind does not allow of several perceptions at one and the same time, it would be impossible to think and speak ; for thought and speech consist in the comparison ot two or more ideas. Now, how is it possible to compare ideas which are not both at once present in the mind ? You allow that we can experience more than one sensation at a time ; for example, we can perceive the colour and shape of a body at the same time ; why not also abstract ideas ? Does not memory employ two ideas present at the same time in the mind the actual idea, and the remembrance of the former ? For my part, I think that is why a good judgment and a good memory are rarely found 1 Racine, Ph^dre l Acte v, Scfcne vu LETTER ON THE DEAF AND DUMB 189 together. A good memory presupposes a great facility in embracing various ideas at one and the same moment or in rapid succession ; and this gift interferes with the tranquil examination of a small number of ideas which the mind ought to contem- plate with fixed attention. A mind stored with a huge variety of things is like a library of odd volumes ; it is like one of these German compila- tions bristling with Hebrew, Arabic, Greek, or Latin quotations put together without judgment or taste ; which are ponderous as it is, and which will grow more and more ponderous, and grow none the better ; a store full of analyses and appreciations and ill-digested works, and shops of mixed goods where the memorandum alone is in order ; a commentary where we scarcely ever find what we want, but often what we don't want, and almost always what we want is lost in a heap of rubbish. It follows from the foregoing statements there is not, and perhaps there cannot be, inversion in the mind, especially if the object contemplated be an abstract one ; and though a Greek may say : w/ciycrcu okufj.'Tna. 6e\eis*, /cayo>, vrj rov$ 8eov$' KOJJ^SOV yap fineni^ Jiodierxus dies attulit. Compare this sentence with the original, and you will find no reason why it should not have been used by him, except that of harmony. Another instance is the great orator's phrase, Mors terrorque civium ac sociorum Romanorum* where it is evident that the natural order required terror morsque. There are a number of other examples I could quote. This leads us to the question whether the natural order should be sacrificed for the sake of harmony. I think this is permissible when the inverted ideas are so close to one another that they strike the ear and mind almost at the same moment ; just as we transpose the fundamental bass into a higher clef to make it more tuneful, although the transposed bass will only be agreeable so long as the ear can distinguish the natural progressions of the funda- mental bass which suggested it. Do not think from this remark that I am a great musician ; it is only two days ago that I began to be one ; but you know how one likes to parade some new accomplishment. I think we might discover several analogies between musical harmony and harmony of style. When, for instance, we are about to describe some great or wonderful events, the harmony of style must be sacrificed or at least disturbed. So we say: 1 " The death and panic of the Roman citizens and their allies." 13 I 9 4 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS Magnum Jovis incrementitml Nee brachia longo Margin* terrarum porrexerat Amphitrite? Ferte titiferrum, date tela, scandite muros* Vita quoquc omnis Omnibus e nervis atque ossibus exsolvatur* Longo sedproximus intervallo? In a similar manner in music we must sometimes shock the ear in order to surprise and please the imagination. We may also observe, that though these licences in the order of words are only per- mitted for the sake of the harmony of style, licences in harmony, on the other hand, are chiefly taken to arouse and give rise in the most natural order to the ideas which the musician wishes to express. In speech we must distinguish between thought arid expression ; if thought is expressed with purity, clarity, and precision, this is quite sufficient for ordinary conversation ; if you add to these a certain distinction in the use of words and a certain rhythm and harmony, you will have a style well fitted for an orator, but you will still be far removed from poetry, especially from the grand style of the epic and the ode. There is a spirit in the poet's lan- guage which moves there and breathes life into each syllable. What is this spirit ? I have felt its pres- ence, but find it difficult to describe. I may say that it states and paints objects at the same time ; 1 Virgil, BucoL, Eclog. iv, v. 49. 2 Ovid, Afefam., lib. i, vv. 13-14. 3 Virgil, Mncid, lib. ix, v. 37. 4 Lucretius, De rerum nat., lib. i, vv. 810-811. 5 Virgil, ^neid^ lib. v, v. 320. LETTER ON THE DEAF AND DUMB 195 it appeals not only to the understanding, but to the soul which it stirs and the imagination that sees and the ear that hears. The lines are not merely a chain of vigorous words which express the thought both forcibly and nobly, but a series of hieroglyphs, one after another, which picture the thought to us vividly. I might say that all poetry is symbolic. But it is not everyone who can understand these symbols. In order to feel their full force we must be, as it were, in the creative mood. The poet says : JSt des fleuves franfaises les eaux ensanglantses Ne portaient que dts marts aux mers epouvaniees^ Does everybody appreciate the value of the first syllable of the word portaient, which paints us the waters swollen with corpses and the stream choked, as it were, by this obstacle? And in the second syllable of the word, does everyone see the mass of waters and dead bodies subsiding and moving out to sea ? The terror of the sea is brought before us all in the word tpouvanttes, but the stress laid on the third syllable brings before me the vast extent of the ocean. Again, the poet says : Soupire^ 'etend les bras, ferme fosil tt fend&rt? All exclaim, ' ' How fine ! " but it is not by counting the syllables on one's fingers that we can judge how fortunate the poet was, when expressing a sigh, to have such a word as soupire with its long-drawn sound. We read t end les frras, but we hardly realise 1 Voltaire, Hcnriade, chant ii, v. 357. 2 Boileau, Lutrin, chant ii, v. 164. 196 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS how the impression of length and lassitude is ex- pressed by the long monosyllable bras y and the * * outstretched arms " fall so reposefully on the ear at the close of the first hemistich of the line. Do we notice the rapid movement of the eyelid in ferine Vml and the almost imperceptible change from wakefulness to sleep at the close of the second hemistich ferine fceil et s'endoitt The cultivated reader will of course observe that the poet has four actions to represent, and that his line is divided into four parts ; that the two last actions are closely interrelated, and that they have scarcely an interval between them ; and that the two last and corresponding parts of the line are also closely linked, united as they are by the rapidity of the movement of the penultimate part and by a conjunction ; that each of the actions takes only its proper proportion of time in the verse ; and that as all four actions are comprised in this small space, the poet has expressed their rapid succession in nature. That is the kind of problem that the poet's genius solves unconsciously ; but do his readers realise his skill? Certainly not; and I shall not therefore be surprised if those readers of Boileau (and there are many) who have not understood the meaning of his symbols laugh at my commentary, and, remembering the Chef-d?ceuvre y the shaking is less rapid and also less like the movement of frowning brows. " Trembles with its close" represents pro- cumbit humi bos fairly well, though the last word of my line is less heavy and emphatic than bos y which is a greater contrast with the word humi than close is with the short words immediately preceding it. Virgil's monosyllable is thus more isolated than mine, and the fall of his ox heavier and more com- plete than the close of my line. An observation I may make here, which is just as apposite as the, speech of the Emperor of Mexico .in the chapter about coaches in Montaigne, 2 is that people had a singular veneration for the ancients, 1 .'Knfirf lib. v, v. 481. 2 Essais, liv. iii, ch. vi. LETTER ON THE DEAF AND DUMB 201 and a great fear of Boileau, when they asked him if the three following lines of Homer, Zeu irdrep, dAAo, cru pvcrcu {JIT yepos vtas *A^ata>j/ * TLofya-ov S* aWp-qv, Sos S* o^OaXj^OifTLV iBecrQai ' 'Ev Se Acte v, Scene vl 2o6 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS contrasts with their present condition I The nodding of a horse's head, as it jogs wearily along, is imitated in a certain syllabic nutation in the line itself : E&il morne maintenant et la fete baisste. But see how the poet brings all these details round to his hero : Ses superbes coursiers^ etc. . . . Semblafent se conformtr a sa triste pcnste. The word " seemed" seems too cautious for a poet, for it is well known that animals attached to man are affected by the signs of his joy or sorrow : the elephant is affected by the death of his driver, the dog mingles his voice with his master's, and the horse is affected if his driver is sad. Racine's description is therefore true to life : it is a noble description and a poetic picture which a painter might reproduce successfully. Poetry, painting, good taste, and truth are all united for Racine and against the Abb6 de Bernis' critique. 1 But if we were taught at Louis le Grand to notice all the beauties of this passage of Racine's tragedy, we were also told that they were out of place in the mouth of Theram&ne, and that Th6se would have had some excuse for stopping him and saying : cc Enough of my son's chariot and horses; tell me 1 [In an addendum to this Letter Diderot apologises for his criticism of the Abb de Bernis. He was at first told by a friend, who was present at the meeting of the French Academy, that the Abb6 de Bernis had criticised these lines of Racine's as both misplaced and bad in them- selves. He was afterwards informed that the Abb merely criticised them as misplaced ; and, far from claiming this criticism as original, he quoted the lines as one of the most familiar instances of such mis- placed eloquence.] LETTER ON THE DEAF AND DUMB 207 about him. " It was not thus, the celebrated Poree told us, that Antilochus announced the death of Patroclos to Achilles. Antilochus approaches the hero with tears in his eyes, and tells him the terrible news in a few words : < Patroclos is no more. They are fighting for his body. Hector has his armour." There is more of the sublime in these two lines of Homer than in all the pompous declamation of Racine. c * Achilles, you have no longer a friend, and your armour is lost." At these words we all feel that Achilles must rush into the fray. When a passage sins against truth and propriety, it is not beautiful, either in tragedy or in epic. The details in Racine's lines would only be suitable in the mouth of a poet describing the death of one of his heroes. So our learned professor of rhetoric taught us. He possessed both taste and intelligence, and it might be said of him that he was the "last of the Greeks." But this Philopcemen fell into the same mistake as people make to-day : he filled his works too full of cleverness, and kept his taste for other people's works. To return to the Abb6 de Bernis. Did he only wish to maintain that Racine's description was out of place ? That is exactly what Father Poree taught us thirty pr forty years ago. Or did he wish to hold up the passage I have quoted as an example of bad taste ? That is an original idea, but is it justified ? I am told that there are many well-expressed and well-reasoned passages in the Abb6 de Bernis' dis- course : you are more likely to know this than I, as 208 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS you always take the opportunity of hearing such things. If it happens the Abbe de Bernis' discourse does not contain the offending passage I have just spoken of, and I have received an imperfect account of it, that will make another instance of the utility of a letter for the use of those who hear and speak. Wherever the language of signs is to be seen, whether in a line of poetry or on an obelisk, whether in a work of imagination or of mystery, it requires a high degree of imagination and penetration to understand it. But if it is so difficult to understand poetry, why is it not more difficult to write poetry ? I shall be told that c * everyone writes poetry," but I shall reply, * * Hardly anyone writes poetry. " Every imitative art has its own alphabet of signs, and I much wish some man of taste and intelligence would make a study of them and compare them. The beauties of one poet have oftentimes been com- pared with those of another. But one task is still un- attempted to collect the beauties of poetry, paint- ing and music, and show their analogies with one another ; to explain how the poet, the painter anc the musician will express the same idea; to seiz< upon their most fleeting images of expression anc examine the likeness, if there is a likeness, betweei the imagery of the different arts. I should advis< you to add this as a chapter to your Fine Art reduced to a Single Principle, and I should also lik you to include, at the beginning of your book, chapter to define in what tfee beauty of nature coi LETTER ON THE DEAF AND DUMB 209 sists. 1 For some people are of opinion that for lack of one of these chapters your treatise is without a firm foundation, and for lack of the other of little practical use. Tell them, sir, the different methods of the arts in treating the same subject, and tell them it is false that nature is only ugly when out of place. They ask me why an old gnarled and twisted oak, with its branches lopped, and which I should have felled if it grew near my door, is just the tree a painter would set by my cottage door, if he had to paint it ? Is the oak beautiful or ugly ? Which is right the owner or the painter ? There is no subject of imitative art which does not arouse this and other difficulties. They also want to know why a scene which is admirable in a poem is not at all suitable for a painting? In those fine lines of Virgil : Interea magno misceri mitrmure pontitm Emissamque hiemem sensit Neptunus^ et imis Stagna refusa vadis ; graviter commotus et alto Prospidens, summa pladdum caput exiulit unda;* they ask why it is the painter cannot seize the striking moment when Neptune raises his head 1 Diderot used to call Batteux* book a headless book, because after he had reduced all the fine arts to a single principle that of imitating the beauty of nature, he never explained what the beauty of nature consisted in. Naigeon, Memoires* 2 Meantime the turmoil of the main The Tempest loosened from its chain ; The waters of the nether deep Upstarting from their tranquil sleep On Neptune broke : disturbed he hears, And, quickened by a monarch's fears, His calm broad brow o'er ocean rears. d^ lib. i, v. 128 (frs. Conington). 14 2fo DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS above the waves ? Why should the god, who then looks like a decapitated man, cut such a poor figure on the water, when the effect in the poem was so impressive? Why is it that what appeals to our imagination in poetry will not please our eyes when painted ? Perhaps there is one beauty of nature for the painter and another for the poet ? Heaven knows what conclusions they will draw from this theory. I hope you will deliver me from these busy bodies ; meantime, I am going to give you a single example of the imitation of one subject in nature by poetry, painting and music* The subject is a dying woman. The poet will say : #, graves oculos conata adtollere, rursus Deficit* Infixum stridit sub pectore vulnus Ter sese adtollens cubitoque adnixa levamt ; Ter revoluta toro est oculisque errantibus alto Qu&sivit c&lo lucem, ingemuitque referta ; 1 or Vita quoque omnis Omnibus e nervis atque ossibus exsofoatur? The musician will begin by descending a semitone (a) : Ilia, graves oculos conata adtollere^ rursus deficit ; then he will go up a fifth, and after a rest, by the still more difficult interval of a tritone (ft). 1 The dull eyes ope, as drowned by sleep, Then close ; the death wound gurgles deep Thrice on her arm she raised her head, Thrice sank exhausted on "the bed. Stared with blank gaze aloft, around For light, and groaned as light she found. Virgil, Mneid, lib. iv, v. 688 (trs. Conington). 2 ' And life break wholly up out of all the sinews and bones. Lucretius, de Rerum Nat** lib. i, w. 810, Su. LETTER ON THE DEAF AND DUMB 211 Ter sese adtollens will go up a semitone (c) : Oculis errantibus alto quasivit ccelo lucem. This little interval will express the ray of light This is the iLxemple =J=t me -nuzinrs & m&ryeiix if ^f tjf. \j 7 ^ ; f e. FIG. 8. dying woman's last effort. After this she will sink by scale (d) : Revoluta tore est. She will expire at last, and breathe her last by an interval of a semitone (e) : Vita quoque omnis omnibus e nervis atquc ossibus 2i2 DJDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS exsolvatur. Lucretius expresses the dying away of her strength by the weight of the two spondees exsolvatur ; and the musician will express it by two minims, tied (/) : and the cadence on the second of the minims will give a very striking imitation of the vacillating motion of a dying lamp. Now look at the painter's method of expression, and you will recognise the exsolvatur of Lucretius in the legs, the right arm, and the left hand. The painter who can express but a moment in time has not been able to represent so many symptoms of dissolution as the poet, but they are much more affecting; the painter shows *us reality, whereas the expressions of the poet and the musician are but symbols. When the musician is an artist, the ac- companiment either emphasises and strengthens the melody, or brings in new ideas which the subject demands and which the melody cannot express. Thus the first bars of the bass express a gloomy harmony, made up by a superfluous chord of the seventh, placed as it were outside the ordinary rules and followed by another chord, discordant in sound and of a diminished fifth (g\ The rest will consist of a series of minor sixths and thirds (A), which are descriptive of exhaustion of strength and prepare the mind for its total extinction. It Is the equivalent of Virgil's spondees : Alto qu&sivit c 47), where Voltaire summarises the case.] 1 Art. " Condillac," Encyclopedia Briiannica, vol. vi, pp. 849-851 (nth edition). APPENDIX BLINDNESS FROM the Encyclop&dia of Diderot and d'Alembert, vol. i, p. 870. The translation is that which appeared in Select Essays from the Encyclopedy, pp. 132-147, London (1782), in which it is attributed to d'Alem- bert. The translation has been revised and corrected. In the translation, two passages which were omitted have been inserted, i.e. the sentence, " If we except certain passages which are not immediately connected with the subject and may offend pious ears/' and the paragraphs, "Imagine a square "to ''Philosophers and beginners would have found it useful." BLINDNESS ONE may be born blind, or become so through acci- dent or malady. It is not our intention here to treat either of the diseases of the eye, or of other accidents that may occasion a loss of sight. We shall confine ourselves to make philosophical reflexions upon blindness, through the ideas of which we are 326 APPENDIX 227 deprived by it as well as through the advantage acquired by the other senses in consequence of it. From the known truth of the sense of seeing being more fitted to distract us by the diversified qualities of objects which it presents to us at once, it follows that they who are deprived of this faculty must naturally, for the most part, apply with a closer attention to the objects which fall under their other senses. And this is the principal reason of that delicacy of touch and hearing that has been observed in some blind people, which is by no means the effect of a real superiority in these two senses ; whereby nature means, as it were, to compensate in some sort for their loss of sight. So true is this position, that a person become blind through accident finds often in the succour of the other senses a resource which he knew not of before ; and this is to be ascribed solely to that person's being less distracted and become more capable of attention. But it is chiefly in persons born blind that we are to remark (if such an expression may be allowed) the miracles of blindness. An anonymous author published in the year 1749 a little philosophical work, very elegantly written, and entitled, Letter on Blindness for the use of those who can see ; with this motto : " Possunt quia posse videntur," which alludes to the prodigies that have been observed in folks born blind. We purpose to give in this article an extract of that ingenious work, whose 228 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS metaphysical reasoning, though very subtle, is yet true in general, if we except certain passages which are not immediately connected with the subject and which may be offensive to pious ears. 1 The author sets out by making mention of a person born blind with whom he was acquainted, and who is probably still alive. This extraordinary man, who lived at Puisaux in Gatinais, was both chemist and musician. He taught his son to read with characters in relievo. He could judge with exactness of symmetry. But it is very likely that the idea of symmetry, which is with us in many respects but a matter of mere convention or agree- ment, is still more so to him* The definition which he gives of a looking-glass has something very singular. "It is," according to him, "a machine, by means whereof things are exhibited in relievo out of themselves." This definition indeed may appear absurd to a blockhead who has eyes ; but a true philosopher, however keen-sighted, will pro- nounce it to be no less subtle than surprising. " Had Descartes been born blind," says our author, "he might be proud of it." By what a delicate train of ideas must he have been led so far ! Our blind man could have, in this affair, no knowledge but through the medium of his feeling. He conceived, from what he had heard other men relate to him, that it is by the faculty of sight they come to a know- ledge of objects, as in a kindred manner he does by the mediation of feeling : it was the only notion he 1 " If we except . . . ears '* omitted in the original translation. APPENDIX 229 could form to himself. He had learned, moreover, that a man cannot see his face, though he can touch it. Sight then, in his sense, must have been a species of feeling or touching, that extends itself to any proper objects that are different from our countenance and placed at a distance from it. Be- sides, the sense of touching or feeling in this case excited in him the idea of a relievo. Therefore, adds he, "a looking-glass is a machine that places us in relievo out of ourselves. " Let it be observed, that the words in relievo are by no means redundant here; for, had the blind man simply said, "which places us out of ourselves," it would have been an absurdity ; because how can we conceive an object that is to 'double itself? The words in relievo here are only applied to the surface ; wherefore by " our- selves being placed in relievo out of ourselves," nothing more is meant than the representation of the surface of our bodies being made out of our- selves. The blind man must have been induced by his manner of reasoning to think that feeling represents to him only the surface of bodies, and that therefore the species of touching or feeling called sight gives us but an idea of the relievo, or the surface of bodies, without giving that of their solidity ; the words in relievo here meaning no more than surface. I own here that the blind man's attempt at an explanation, notwithstanding this restriction, is an enigma to him ; but a pleasure that must hence result to all reflecting minds is to observe (consider- 230 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS ing his situation) the very ingenious method employed by him to diminish, and, as far as by him practicable, to solve the enigma. It must strike everybody that mirrors, and every kind of glasses which enlarge, diminish, or multiply objects, were impenetrable mysteries to him. c c He asked if the glass that increased objects was shorter than that which lessened them ; or if that which drew them near was less than that which threw them off at a distance ; and not being able to conceive how the other ourselves were impalpable to feeling, he cried out, " I perceive that two senses are put in contradiction to one another by the means of a little machine ; another, more perfect, would make them agree ; and a third, still more perfect and less perfidious, would make all those phantoms disappear and convince us that we had been in error." What philosophical conclusions might not a person born blind be enabled to bring against the fallacy of our senses ! He defines the eyes to be an organ on which the air causes the same effect as a stick upon the hand. The author we abstract from here observes that this definition has some resemblance with that of Descartes, who in his Dioptrics compares the eye to a blind man that touches objects at a distance with his stick. The rays of light are the sticks of the clear-sighted. Our blind man's memory of sounds is to a most amazing degree ; and he distinguishes among the variety of voices with as much accuracy and quick- APPENDIX 23! ness as those who see can among that of faces. The succour which he derives from his other senses, and the very surprising use which he makes thereof, to the astonishment of all whom he has any concern with, render him almost indifferent about the loss of sight. He is sensible enough that in some circum- stances he has advantages over those who can see ; which make him, instead of being desirous of sight, to wish, as an equivalent thereto, for longer arms. He addresses himself directly towards the place whence any noise or voice affects his ear. He judges of the proximity of fire by the degree of heat ; of the plenitude of vessels by the noise which liquors make as they are poured from them ; of the nearness of bodies by the action of the air upon his face : he can distinguish an open street from a cul- de-sac (one that has no passage through it) ; which proves that the air, relatively to him, is never in an absolute state of rest, and that his countenance is instinctively sensible of the least vicissitude in the atmosphere. He judges wonderfully well of the weight of bodies and the capacity of vessels ; he has trained his arms to serve him as exact scales or balances, and his fingers as compasses that never deceive him. The smoothness of bodies has as many variations for him as the sounds of the voice. He judges of beauty by the touch ; and, what is singular, he makes the sound of the person's voice, with their manner of pronouncing, come in for a share of this judgment. He executes several little works in the turning 232 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS way and with a needle ; he takes a level with a square ; he puts together or takes asunder pieces of common machinery ; he performs pieces of music, the notes and their value being first told him ; he estimates, with much more precision than we do, the progress of time, and that by the succession of actions and thoughts. He has an implacable hatred of thieves ; and the reason, no doubt, arises from the difficulty, or rather impossibility, in which he is to perceive when he is robbed ; he has but little, or rather scarce any, notion of what modesty consists in ; he looks upon clothes as necessary for protecting our bodies from the injuries of the air, but he cannot comprehend why certain parts of the body should be covered preferably to others. " Wherefore," says the author we abridge from, " Diogenes would not have ranked as a philosopher in the opinion of our blind hero." In fine, the exterior appearance of worldly pomp, with which the generality of mankind are so much affected, impose not upon him in the least, which in the kingdom of reason is no despicable article." We pass over in silence a great number of very subtle and refined reflections made by the author we quote from upon the French blind man, to proceed to what he says of another celebrated personage in the same situation ; and that is the famous Saunderson of England, a professor of mathematics at CambridgCj who died a few years ago. When an infant, he lost his sight by the small-pox, and so early that he did not remember to have ever APPENDIX 233 seen. He had no more ideas of light than a person born blind. Notwithstanding his misfortune, he made such a surprising progress in the mathematics that the professorship thereof was conferred on him by the above-mentioned University. His lectures were exceedingly clear ; and the reason assigned for it is, that he used to address himself to his pupils as if they were all deprived of sight : whence it followed, of course, that the blind teacher who could explain his meaning clearly to blind pupils must have a great advantage with those who could see, from their quickness of conceiving him. He taught his scholars the calculations he had made. Imagine a wooden square divided by perpendicular lines into four small squares ; suppose this square pierced with nine holes capable of receiving pins of the same length and thickness, but of which some had larger heads than others. Saunderson had a great number of these little squares traced on a large board. To denote the cipher nought, he would place a large-headed pin in the centre of one of these squares, and no pin in the other holes. To denote the number i, he placed a small-headed pin in the centre of a little square. To denote the number 2, he placed a large-headed pin in the centre, and above, in the same line, a small pin in the corresponding hole. To denote 3, a large-headed pin in the centre, a small-headed pin in the centre, and a small-headed pin in a hole above to the right ; and so on. Thus Saunderson, when touching a small square, perceived at once the 234 DIDEROT'S PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS number 'it denoted, and on glancing at the following table we shall see his method of addition by means of these small squares : 12345 23456 34567 45678 56789 67890 78901 89012 90123 Running his fingers down each vertical row of figures from top to bottom, he added up in the ordinary manner, and marked the sum by means of pins placed in squares at the foot of the above numbers. The same board divided into squares served for geometrical demonstrations. He placed large-headed pins in the holes in the direction of a straight line, thus forming polygons, etc. Saunderson also left some instruments which were of use to him in his study of geometry, but how he used them is not known. He published his Elements of Algebra, equal to the best that has been published on this subject, but, as our author observes, elements of his geometry would have been even more interesting. I have heard from a person of his acquaintance that the demonstrations of the properties of solid bodies, APPENDIX 235 which are usually a matter of considerable difficulty, were child's play to him. His mind moved in a pyramid, an icosahedron, from one angle to another, with the greatest ease ; he imagined planes and sec- tions in these solids without any effort. Perhaps for this reason the demonstrations which he might have given would have proved more difficult than those of a clear-sighted geometrician ; but his demonstra- tions on plane geometry would in all probability be extremely clear, and perhaps singular. Philosophers and beginners would have profited by them. Although it may appear very singular to the many that he gave lectures upon optics, yet to philo- sophical minds the miraculous of this affair dis- appears, on reflecting that a blind man, without any idea of light or colours, may give lectures upon optics, in proceeding like the geometricians who look upon the rays of light as straight lines that ought to be disposed of and arranged according to certain laws in order to cause the phenomenon of vision, as well as those observable in mirrors, optic glasses, etc. Saunderson in running his hand over a series of medals could distinguish the false from the true, even when they were so well counterfeited as even to deceive the practised eye of a connoisseur ; he could judge of the exactness of mathematical instru- ments by running his fingers over the divisions. He was, like the before-mentioned blind man, sensible of the least vicissitudes in the atmosphere ; and he perceived (in calm weather especially) the presence 236 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS of objects near him. As he sat one day in his garden meditating on astronomical observations, he distinguished, by the impression of the air on his countenance, the different times when the sun was covered with clouds and when it was not ; which is so much the more extraordinary, as that he was deprived not only of sight but of the organ. The pretended history of Saunderson's last mo- ments, printed in England, is an absolute imposi- tion ; which, though held by many learned men to be highly criminal against the majesty of science, might be deemed only a stroke of mere pleasantry were it not occasioned by so solemn and respectable a subject. Our author afterwards treats in a cursory manner of several other blind personages who in spite of the loss of one sense have made a wonderful progress in the arts and sciences. He farther observes, and not improbably, that the famous Tiresias, who is said to have become blind because he had penetrated into the secrets of the gods and could predict future events, was in all likelihood some celebrated blind philosopher, whose name fabulous history hath transmitted down to us. Perhaps he was the most renowned philosopher of his time, because he could foretell eclipses (which to an ignorant people must appear astonishing). His becoming blind towards the latter end of his life was doubtless occasioned by too continued an application that over-fatigued his eyes in making such a variety of nice observations, as hath since indeed been the case with Galileo and Cassini. APPENDIX 237 There have been many instances of people born blind being restored to sight ; as, for example, that young lad, about thirteen years old, whom Mr Cheselden, a celebrated surgeon at London, re- lieved from the cataract that had rendered him blind from his birth. This great operator curiously observed the progressive manner of his beginning to see, which he published in No. 42 of the Philo- sophical Transactions, and in the fifty-fifth number of the Toiler, with his remarks thereon. Here follows an extract of those remarks* from the third volume of Natural History, by Messieurs de Buffon and d'Aubenton : " This youth, notwithstanding his blindness, could distinguish the day from the night, as can all those who are blinded by cataract. He could distinguish any strong light, as he could also the colours black, white, and scarlet ; but he could not discern the form of bodies. The operation was first made upon one eye. As soon as the young patient began to see, all the objects before him seemed to him as if they were applied to his eyes ; and those that appeared the more pleasing to him, although he could give no reason for it, were such as had a regular form. He did not, however, know the colours, which, while blind, he could distinguish by the aid of a strong light. He could not discriminate one object from another, however different the forms were. When the objects, which he had known before by feeling, were presented to him, he considered attentively in order to recognise them ; but, all of a sudden, a 238 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS general act of oblivion followed from the multi- tude of things that crowded in upon him for admiration. '* He was much surprised in not finding those persons handsomer whom he had loved more than others. He was a long time before he could be made to comprehend how pictures represented solid bodies. He at first looked upon them as planes differently coloured ; but when he was undeceived, and on applying his hands to them, discovered nothing beside surface, he asked whether it was the sight or the touch which had deceived him. He expressed great surprise that in a little space the picture of an object much larger than the space could be contained ; as, for example, the human counten- ance in a miniature portrait, which appeared to him equally impossible as to make a quart contain a bushel. "At first he could bear but a very small quantity of light, and saw all objects very large ; but by degrees the first seen looked smaller, as he accus- tomed himself to see larger. Although he very well knew the chamber in which he was to be of less dimensions than the house, yet he could not conceive why the house should appear larger than the chamber. * * Before the restitution of his sight, he was but very little anxious about the recovery of this addi- tional sense to him, because he knew not the loss of it, and was conscious of himself that in some articles he enjoyed peculiar advantages unknown to others who APPENDIX 239 could see. But as soon as he came to view objects distinctly, then he felt real transports of joy. ' ' About a year after the first operation, the second was performed upon the other eye, and was crowned with equal success. He saw at first, with this second eye, the objects much larger than they appeared to the other ; but, however, not so large as they had appeared at first to it, after the opera- tion a year before. When he looked steadfastly on an object with both his eyes, he said that the object appeared to him as big again as when he looked at it only with his first eye." Mr Cheselden mentions several others born blind, whom he had freed from the cataract, and observed in them the same phenomena, without entering into a like detail He remarks that from their not having been used to move their eyes during the state of blind- ness, it was but by degrees that they learned how to direct them towards objects. From the result of these experiments it must clearly appear that the sense of seeing arrives at perfection but by slow degrees, and is at first very confused ; and that we learn to see, pretty nearly as we learn to speak. A new-born babe, that opens its eyes for the first time to the light, feels, no doubt, the same progressive emotions which have been observed in the lad born blind. By the agency of feeling and custom the erroneous judgments of infant sight are corrected gradually. Let us now return to our author, who says : " We seek for people born blind, in order to examine 2A&DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS was discovered. I made use of it, and explained to the dumb man that he was mistaken, and that I had escaped though he did not expect me to. But he, by pointing his finger at the spectators one after another, and making a motion of the lips, accom- panied by a sweeping movement of his arms in the direction of the door and the tables, replied that it was no credit to me to have got out of my difficulty by calling in all and sundry to my help. His gestures were so significant that no one could mis- understand him, and the popular expression "all and sundry " * occurred to many at the same time : this expression was definitely translated by our dumb man's gestures. You know, at least you have heard, of a singular machine with which the inventor proposed to give sonatas in colour. I thought that if anyone could appreciate a performance of ocular music, and could judge of it without prejudice, it would be a man born deaf and dumb. I therefore took my friend to the house in the rue St Jacques, where the operator and the machine with colours was exhibited. Ah, sir, you would never guess the kind of impression that it made on him, nor the ideas it suggested. You see that it was impossible to explain to him beforehand the nature and marvellous powers of the harpsichord; and, having no idea of sound, this instru- ment with colours could not suggest to him any musical impressions. The purpose of the machine 1 [Consumer le fiers, le qitart ct Us peasants; literally, "the third, the quarter, and the passers-by."] APPENDIX 241 angle of a cube, which presses on his hand in an irregular manner, is to appear to his eyes what it appears in the cube. Our above-quoted author, who founds his opinion on Cheselden's experiment, inclines to believe (and with reason) that a person born blind must at first see all objects in a very confused manner, and that, so far from distinguishing the globe from the cube, he "Will not have a distinct perception of the two different figures. He believes, however, that in the long run, and without the assistance of touching, the new spectator will learn to make a distinction between the two figures. The reason which he alleges, and that cannot be easily refuted, is that, the blind person not being necessitated to employ his touch to distinguish colours one from another, the limits of colours will at length suffice to teach him how to discriminate the form and the contour ot different objects. In fine, he will see a globe and a cube ; that is, a circle and a square. But the tact, or sense of touching, having no relation whatever to that of sight, he will not be able to guess that one of those bodies is what he calls a globe and the other a cube : so vision will by no means recall to his memory a sensation which he had received by the tact. Let us now suppose him to be told that one of these two bodies is what by tact he felt to be a globe, and the other a cube : will he be able to distinguish them? The answer given by our ingenious author is, that an uninstructed and grossly ignorant person would hastily pronounce at all 16 2 4 2 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS events ; but that a metaphysical or geometrical mind, such as Saunderson's, would proceed with a cautious examination of those figures ; and when, by the supposition of certain lines therein, he would find that he can demonstrate In the one all the properties of the circle which he had learned by the tact, and in the other all those of a square, he would immediately be tempted to pronounce, " That is the globe, and this is the square." However, if he be prudent, he will be dubious of giving so pre- cipitate a judgment, and thus reflect within himself : "Perhaps, on an application of my hand to these two figures, they will be mutually transformed one into the other, so that the first figure might serve for my demonstrating the properties of a circle to blind folk; and those of a square, to such as can see." But a Saunderson would reply in the negative : * * I am in error : they to whom I demonstrated the properties of a circle and a square, in whom the faculties of seeing and hearing perfectly agreed, understood me very well, although they did not touch the figures upon which I made the demon- stration : they were satisfied with seeing them. They did not see a square when I felt a cube : no ; for If they had, we should never have understood each other. But since they all understood me, it Is clear that all men see alike. Therefore I see a square what they saw a square and I felt to be a square ; and by a parity of reason, I see a circle what I felt to be a circle." APPENDIX 243 We have here, in complaisance to our quoted author, substituted circle to globe, and square to cube ; because there is much reason to believe that he who makes use of his eyes for the first time sees nothing but surfaces, and knows not what projection is ; for the projection of a body consists in some of its points being more advanced towards us than others. It is then by experience jointly with the tact, and not the sight alone, that we are enabled to judge of distances. From all that has been said of the globe and the cube, or of the circle and the square, let us conclude with our author, that there are circumstances where the reasoning and experience of others furnish a new perspicuity to the faculty of seeing through its relationship with the tact, and give assurance to the eyes that they are in perfect harmony with each other. The letter-writer concludes with some reflexions on what might be the case of a person who should have seen from his birth, but was deprived of tact or feeling ; and of another, in whom the senses -of feeling and seeing should be in a perpetual contra- diction with each other. But in order to avoid pro- lixity here, we refer our readers to his reflexions ; but which recall to our memory another, made by him in the middle of his work, and of the same tendency, viz. : C( If a person," says he, " who had seen but for a day or two, were to find himself in the midst of a blind people, he must take the resolution either of holding his tongue, or of passing for a fool ; 244 DIDEROTS PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS because every day he would think he was communi- cating some new mystery, and such only to them, but which their choice spirits would treat with contempt. The advocates for, and defenders of, religion might perhaps derive some advantages from their cause from an incredulity so obstinate and so ill-grounded. " With this reflexion we close the present article ; and it is sufficient to counterbalance several others, scattered throughout the work, that indeed seem to border on infidelity. INDEX Algebra (see Elements of Algebra). Article, the origin of the definite, 182-184, 2I 6. Augustine, St., 60. Aveugle (article in the Encyclo- pedia}, 13, 226-244. Batteux, Charles, Abbe, 23, 209 note. Berkeley, George, Bishop of Cloyne, 104. Bernis, Frangois Joachim de Pierre de, Abbe, 205-207, 216. Bible, tne authenticity of, 52-53. BufTon, George Louis Leclerc, Comte de, 2, 237. Calculating machines, Saunder- son's, 90-99, 219, 233- 234. Castel, Father, his ocular music, 170-172. Characteristics, 221. Cheselden, William, 7, 125, 132, 225, 237, 239, 241, Cicero, 55-56, 67, 180-182. Clarke, Samuel, no. Condillac, Etienne Bonnot de, 7, 24-25, 104-105, 119-120, 122, 126, 133, 223-225. d ! Alembert, Jean le Rond, 3, 5, 137, 226. tfAleniberfs. Dream, 4. Darwin, Erasmus, I. Daviel, Jacques, 144-145. Deaf and dumb alphabet, 8-9, 89-90. de Puisieux (see Puisieutf , Madame de), 24S de Reaumur (see Reaumur). de Salignac (see Salignac, Melanie de). Descartes, Rene, 34, 64, 73, 102, 203. Design, argument from, 5-6, 10- 15, 3 6 ~39, 109-114. de Vandeul (see Vandeul, Madame de). Diderot, Denis, life of, 1-4. English influence on, 2. works, 2-4. Didymus of Alexandria, 108, 220. Dioptrics, 73. Elements of Algebra, 8, 16, 17, 99, 104, 106, 234. Elements of the Philosophy of Newton, 7, 225. Encyclopaedia, 3, 6, 23, 226. Essay concerning Human Under- standing, 222-223. Essay on Merit and Virtue (see Inquiry concerning Virtue and Merit). Essay on the Origin of Human Knowledge, 7, 104-105, 119, 122, 126, 224. Eusebius the Asiatic, 108. Fine Arts reduced to a Singh Principle, 23, 158, 208. French language, 190-191, 217- 218. Galileo, 102. Gesture-language, 25, 163-167, 175, 214. Gregory the Great, 52. 246 DIDEROT 'S PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS Harmony in music, 217. Harmony of style, 192-193. Hebrew language, 203-204 . Holmes, Gervase, 10, 18-19, 108-114. Homer, 199-203. Inchlif, William, 115-116. Indiscreet Jewels, 2, 20, 23. Inquiry concerning Virtue and Merit i 2, 19. Inversion, in language, 160-163, 176, 178, 180-182, 189- .. 192- Julian, edict of the Emperor, 50- 52. Lamarck, Jean Baptiste Pierre Antoine de Monet, Cheva- lier de, 1-2. Language, development of, 215- 216. Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, 110- III. Le Sage, I74-I7S- Letter of Mr Gervase Holmes to the Author of the Letter on the Blind, 19. Letter on the Blind, 2-3, 6-15, 20, 23-24, 68-141, 158, 227. Letter on the Blind> Addition to, 142-157. Letter on the Deaf and Dumb, 3, 23-25, 160-218. Life of Saunderson, by Dr Inchlif, 10, 115-116. Locke, John, 9, 64, 119-120, 221, 224-225. Longinus, 201-202, 216. Memoirs of the Life and Character of Dr Nicholas Saunderson (in Saunderson's Algebra}, 16-17. Method of Fluxions applied to a Select Number of Useful Problems, 17. Miracles, 53-62. Molyneux, problem of, 118-123, 222-223, 240-243. Montaigne, Michel de, 41 -43, 64, 140. Montgeron, Corre de, 60-62. Muet de convention (theoretical mute), 24-25, 163-166, 214-215. Natural History, 237. Newton, Isaac, 7, 15, 34, 102, IIO-TII. Nicaise of Mechlin, 1 08, 220. Pascal, Blaise, 32. 'Philosophic Thoughts, 3, 4-6, 20, 27-67. Puisaux, the blind man of, 8, 69- 81, 228-232. Puisieux, Madame de, 6-7, 19-20. Racine, Jean, 205-206. Reaumur, Rene Antoine Fer- chault, Seigneur de, 7, 20, 68-69, 137. Saint- Hilaire, Geoffroy, i. Salignac, Mlanie de, 146-157. Saunderson, Dr Nicholas, 7-8, 10, 13, 15-19, oo-"6, 137-138, 232-236. Sceptic's Walk, The, 3, 6. Select Parts of Professor Sounder- son's Elements of Algebra, 17- Shaftesbury, Earl of, 221. Symbolism in poetry, 195-200, 208. Thoughts on the Interpretation of Nature, 4, 12-13. Transformism, I, 11-13, 111-114. Treatise on the Sensations, 24-25) 224-225. Treatise on Systems, 105, 119, 132, 224. Vandeul, Madame de, 20. Virgil, I97-I99. Voltaire, Francois-Marie Arouet, 7, 14, 225. .isrx>